The Negative Right to Shelter
For over forty years, scholars and advocates have responded to the criminalization of homelessness by calling for a “right to shelter.” As traditionally conceived, the right to shelter is a positive right—an enforceable entitlement to have the government provide or fund a temporary shelter bed for every homeless individual. However, traditional right-to-shelter efforts have failed. Despite the continuing prominence of right-to-shelter rhetoric, only four U.S. jurisdictions have embraced such a right. Moreover, the shelter systems in these jurisdictions are troublingly inadequate, mired in administrative bureaucracy and cabined by strict eligibility limits. The right-to-shelter movement has even proven pernicious. Centering a positive right to shelter in the discourse surrounding homelessness has rendered the weaknesses in shelter offerings invisible, and courts increasingly reify temporary emergency shelters as a justification for criminalizing unsheltered homelessness.
This Article proposes an alternative conception of the right to shelter as a negative right. It outlines a framework for recognizing a fundamental, constitutional right to shelter oneself without government interference. Self-sheltering activities, in this sense, would include everything from the simple use of blankets or bedding to the erection of temporary encampments in public spaces. It situates this new right within the traditions of constitutional due process jurisprudence premised on respecting human dignity. As the Article details, human dignity in the constitutional sense is understood both as ensuring a specific capacity for self-determination, particularly with respect to bodily autonomy and interpersonal relationships, and as protecting against group-based subordination of disfavored classes. These interests are inescapably implicated by the decision to self-shelter while homeless. Recognizing a negative right to shelter is therefore an essential step to protect the dignity of homeless individuals while dismantling the plethora of criminal laws that currently plague them.
Table of Contents Show
Introduction
At age seventeen, I was homeless. As homelessness goes, I had it better than most.
In other ways, my homelessness was typical. Like nearly half of those experiencing homelessness, my circumstances were a product of a turbulent family environment.
There is one other key way in which my experience was typical: I was a criminal.
Urban camping ordinances prevent homeless individuals from taking the most fundamental steps to shelter themselves from their environment. Tents, bedding, and even blankets become telltale signs of criminal activity when used to protect oneself, whether from the elements or from other people.
Had I been arrested for urban camping, my car may have been impounded, the status of my worldly possessions uncertain.
For over forty years, advocates have responded to the criminalization of homelessness by calling for a “right to shelter.”
Courts, however, have recently flipped the script on the right to shelter. In 2018, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals ruled that the Eighth Amendment prohibits criminalizing urban camping unless alternative shelter is reasonably available.
This Article proposes an alternative conception of the right to shelter as a negative right. Recognizing that government-funded shelter services are not a universal solution to the social problem of homelessness, it outlines a framework for recognizing an essential right to shelter oneself without government interference.
The Article upends the traditional conception of a right to shelter by focusing on the right to human dignity guaranteed by the U.S. Constitution’s due process clauses.
Part I examines the criminalization of urban camping and related forms of self-sheltering. It explores the consequences of relying on criminal laws to resolve deep-seated social problems. And it details the long, and largely ineffective, history of constitutional challenges to criminalization. Part II chronicles the history of legislative and litigative efforts to secure a positive “right to shelter” for homeless individuals. Although the most noteworthy of these efforts took place in the 1980s and 1990s, this Part considers how the rhetoric demanding a positive right to government-run or government-funded shelter may continue to infect constitutional litigation about the rights of the homeless. Part III offers a deep exploration of the myriad considerations that inform whether homeless individuals elect to use available shelter services. It demonstrates that some homeless individuals may rationally prefer “self-sheltering”—making do on streets, in public spaces, or in homeless encampments—to the forms of shelter traditionally offered by the state. Part IV then constructs an alternative vision of the “right to shelter” as a negative right to be free from government interference while self-sheltering. It situates this right within the traditions of constitutional due process jurisprudence premised on human dignity. Fundamentally, this Article argues that a proper respect for human dignity requires tolerating the individual preference to self-shelter in public spaces. In a brief coda, Part IV also explores three forms of state regulation of homeless self-sheltering that may survive constitutional scrutiny.
I. Criminalizing Self-Sheltering
On any given night in the United States, an estimated 580,000 people are without a home.
Even these numbers do not capture the enormity of the problem. Point-in-time counts do not include homeless individuals who are sleeping on floors or couches of family and friends, those who intentionally seek to avoid detection, and the temporarily incarcerated.
Most Americans are closer to homelessness than they realize. The United States has a well-documented deficit of affordable housing.
The societal response to this heartbreaking fact has been to meet homelessness with criminalization. Cities and states across the country have passed laws prohibiting acts intrinsically connected to the condition of homelessness.
This Part surveys the criminal response to homelessness, with a particular emphasis on laws outlawing self-sheltering activities, such as urban camping ordinances. It begins by detailing both the origins of criminal laws against homelessness and the recent proliferation of such laws. It then examines the substantial human toll criminal responses inflict on those who are subjected to them. Lastly, this Part reviews the history of legal challenges that have been levied against criminal responses to homelessness, focusing on constitutional arguments grounded in the Fifth, Eighth, and Fourteenth Amendments.
A. The Proliferation of Criminal Laws
Laws against homelessness have existed since the country’s founding.
The justifications for early American vagrancy laws fostered specific stigmas about homelessness that persist to this day.
The constitutionality of vagrancy laws drew heightened attention in the 1960s and 1970s, in part because of a series of police abuses.
Around the same time, however, public attention crystalized on the blight of visible poverty.
As the demographics of homelessness changed, so did its visibility. Because governments refused to fund homeless assistance and actively cut back on social welfare spending, this generation experienced “‘literal homelessness’ with no access to conventional dwellings, such as houses, apartments, mobile homes, rooming houses, or SROs.”
Legislatures responded to this reality by passing a plethora of criminal laws tailored to more narrowly target conduct associated with homelessness.
In the contemporary regime, the most essential forms of criminalizing homelessness are bans on what is known as “urban camping.” These broad prohibitions punish people for devising any form of living arrangement in public spaces.
Punishments for urban camping vary. At the lighter end, some cities enforce urban camping ordinances with purely civil penalties—at least for first-time offenders—consisting of tickets and fines.
Criminal responses to the social problem of homelessness are largely motivated by ignorance of homelessness’s causes and long-standing prejudice against the individuals experiencing it.
Public misperceptions of homelessness have a direct impact on homeless communities because criminal enforcement frequently follows civilian complaints.
B. Criminalization’s Consequences
The legal response to homelessness often differs substantially from the social one. As just noted, the goal of criminalization in many instances is not to sanction morally culpable behavior, but instead to authorize police interventions with homeless populations.
Nevertheless, the criminalization of homelessness has increased the connection between unhoused individuals and the criminal justice system. Nationally, an individual experiencing homelessness is up to eleven times more likely to be arrested than a housed individual.
Meanwhile, criminal responses do nothing to actually combat homelessness. Police have a limited arsenal of tools at their disposal—citations, arrests, and the threat of physical force.
These criminal responses to homelessness tend to entrench poverty, often burdening homeless individuals with fines and fees that can total in the thousands of dollars.
As I have detailed elsewhere, arrests are particularly destructive to homeless individuals.
The costs of policing homelessness through uniformed officers, courts, and jails diverts public money from organizations that could provide genuine services to homeless individuals.
C. Legal Challenges to Criminalization
Ordinances prohibiting urban camping have survived varied legal challenges over the years. As mentioned above, early litigants emphasized procedural defects with the ordinances, such as vagueness and overbreadth. Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville is illustrative. The ordinance at issue was exceptionally broad, criminalizing more than twenty classes of individuals as “vagrants.”
Victories, however, were often short-lived. Ordinances struck down on such grounds were easily repaired and reenacted, resulting in little lasting change in the lived experience of homelessness. Following the Papachristou decision, Jacksonville—like many cities with similar ordinances—recast its prohibitions to focus on more discrete conduct, such as camping, loitering, begging, or creating nuisances.
More recently, legal challenges to camping bans have turned their attention to the Eighth Amendment. The Supreme Court has held that the Eighth Amendment “imposes substantive limits on what can be made criminal.”
Initially, the status-crimes doctrine appeared to be a viable theory for dismantling general vagrancy statutes. In the 1962 case of Robinson v. California, the Supreme Court overturned a law that premised criminal punishments on the status of addiction.
Homeless advocates had comparatively less success leveraging the status-crimes doctrine to reach contemporary prohibitions on urban camping. Relying on the tenuous distinction between a “status” and an “act,” many courts have rejected Eighth Amendment challenges to camping ordinances, because the act of camping is deemed to be volitional, rather than an inescapable incident of homelessness as a status.
One place where Eighth Amendment arguments have recently gained traction, however, is in the Ninth Circuit. In 2006, a panel of that court overturned a Los Angeles camping ban, concluding that homelessness was sufficiently analogous to addiction despite neither being “innate or immutable,” nor “a disease, such as drug addiction or alcoholism.”
Of all legal challenges to urban camping ordinances, substantive due process arguments have been perhaps the least successful. Initially, this seems surprising; the conventional understanding of substantive due process is that it demarcates a sphere of personal liberty within which criminal regulation is constitutionally impermissible.
Historically, such challenges have been rejected due to weaknesses in the briefing or chosen argument, rather than the inapplicability of substantive due process more generally. A few examples are illustrative. In 1996, the Ninth Circuit rejected a due process challenge to a Seattle ordinance that criminalized sitting or lying on sidewalks.
In 2000, the Eleventh Circuit rejected a due process challenge to an urban camping ordinance.
Of the few successful substantive due process challenges, many have relied on the fundamental right to travel.
The history of legal challenges to urban camping ordinances reveals an ever-shifting patchwork of constitutional arguments that homeless advocates may deploy for temporary expediency, but which fail to capture the foundational harms of criminalization. The injustice of urban camping ordinances runs deeper than procedural defects, such as vagueness and overbreadth. Nor is it encapsulated by the counterintuitive right to travel. What individuals experiencing homelessness have so far lacked is a constitutional principle that captures the lived experience of existing at the mercy of the criminal regulatory state.
II. “Right to Shelter” Efforts
As early as the early 1970s, homeless advocates began to turn their attention from constitutional arguments for decriminalization to securing a positive “right to shelter.”
Right-to-shelter advocates advanced on two fronts. They found some limited success in the courts, where they primarily attempted to find a legal hook for the right to shelter in a variety of disparate state constitutional provisions and federal funding contracts.
Despite decades of effort, only four United States jurisdictions currently recognize an enforceable right to shelter, all of which are grounded in legal or political developments between 1979 and 1990.
This Part first details the twin efforts of the right-to-shelter movement before exploring a curious consequence of securing government-provided shelter—increasingly, and counterproductively, courts have cited the availability of such shelter as an additional justification for criminalizing urban camping.
A. Litigating a Right to Shelter
Beginning in the early 1970s, the right-to-shelter movement took to the courts, with little success. Focusing initially on constitutional litigation, homeless advocates contended that the due process and equal protection clauses of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments should be construed to require government-provided shelter for individuals experiencing homelessness.
Despite failure on the federal level, homeless advocates brought similar lawsuits based on state constitutional provisions that are arguably broader than the federal Constitution.
In 1979, the New York State Supreme Court ordered the city and state to provide shelter for all “needy, indigent men” in a landmark decision, Callahan v. Carey.
Faced with a wealth of testimony detailing the gross insufficiency of shelters and the intolerable conditions inside shelters, New York City and the state entered prolonged negotiations with the plaintiffs.
Despite the broad guarantee of shelter in Callahan, eligibility criteria in New York significantly narrow the types of individuals and families that can access the government-provided shelter services. At the state level, services are run through the Office of Temporary and Disability Assistance’s Housing and Support Services program.
In New York City, shelter services are provided through the Department of Homeless Services (DHS), under the Department of Social Services.
New York is not the only state to have found a right to shelter through litigation. West Virginia courts have similarly recognized an enforceable right to temporary emergency shelter in limited circumstances. Under West Virginia law, the state’s Department of Welfare is authorized to institute proceedings to abate any abuse or neglect of a vulnerable adult or to abate an emergency situation.
Pursuant to Hodge, the assistance provided to homeless individuals in West Virginia must be such as “will meet the individual’s needs with the least necessary restrictions on his liberty and civil rights.”
In practical terms, the mandate of Hodge is limited. West Virginia programs based on the Hodge decision require an individual seeking assistance to be over the age of eighteen, to meet a specific definition of “homeless,” and to “lack sufficient resources to obtain needed emergency shelter, food or medical care” in order to be eligible for services.
The West Virginia Department of Health and Human Resources provides a Homeless Services Policy manual.
The federal Department of Health and Human Services notes that West Virginia faces unique challenges in combatting homeless due to the rural nature of the state.
B. Legislating a Right to Shelter
Inspired by the successful litigation in New York, Mitch Snyder—former Wall Street broker and once-homeless founder of the Community for Creative Nonviolence (CCNV)—sought to achieve recognition of the right to shelter in Washington, D.C.
Thus, in 1983, Snyder and CCNV launched an initiative to put the right to shelter on the ballot.
The success of Snyder and CCNV’s efforts would ultimately be short-lived. This first incarnation of the right to shelter only remained on the books in D.C. for five years.
D.C.’s right to shelter was ultimately replaced with the D.C. Emergency Overnight Shelter Amendment Act of 1990. The Act created a statutory right to shelter that depends on environmental factors; it exists only during hypothermic conditions.
D.C. Law 21-141, the Homeless Shelter Replacement Act of 2016 (“2016 Act”), provided the Mayor with authority to appropriate funds to create additional space and resources for the DC General Family Shelter, which houses families experiencing homelessness.
Currently, shelters in D.C. are operated by nonprofit organizations under contract with the Department of Human Services.
Around the same time as D.C., the right to shelter movement reached Massachusetts. In 1983, then-Governor Michael Dukakis signed legislation mandating that every municipality must provide temporary emergency shelter to any family who is eligible for services, every night.
One reason for this discrepancy is that Massachusetts has narrow criteria for shelter eligibility, requiring individuals to prove that their homelessness is due to a preapproved reason.
Such narrow grounds for eligibility pose evident problems. For example, the eligibility rules exclude those who own property worth over $2,500.
Shelter services also deny residents any control over their location. Although Massachusetts has a preference for providing individuals a shelter placement within twenty miles of their hometown, individuals could be offered shelter anywhere in the state if a better placement is unavailable.
The shelter services provided are of dubious quality. The Department of Housing and Community Development (DHCD) outlines four types of potential shelter for eligible families and pregnant women: scattered sites, co-shelter sites, congregate sites, and hotels.
Most recently, California’s Legislature considered—but ultimately rejected—a right to shelter. Following Governor Gavin Newsom’s announcement in 2019 that he would prioritize helping the homeless, Newsom convened his Council of Regional Homeless Advisors, who suggested a “right to shelter” plan modeled after New York City.
Ultimately, the Council put forward a moderate plan calling for an amendment to the California Constitution.
In February 2020, Assembly Bill 3269 was introduced in the California Legislature to enact the Council’s plan.
C. Right to Shelter as a Condition to Criminalization
Right-to-shelter efforts have centered government-provided or government-funded shelter beds in the public discourse about how best to resolve the problem of homelessness. Likewise, two recent decisions by the Ninth Circuit have similarly centered the provision of shelter beds in the legal debates over the criminalization of homelessness. These decisions interpret the Eighth Amendment to prohibit enforcing urban camping laws unless a bed in a local shelter is reasonably available. When a shelter bed is available, these decisions support criminalizing urban camping as a morally culpable “choice” made by homeless individuals. This narrative whitewashes the history of urban camping laws and transforms their justifications in a way that threatens to entrench the criminalization of homeless individuals.
As noted above, early Eighth Amendment challenges to urban camping ordinances found some limited success with the argument that punishing urban camping means punishing the “status” of homelessness.
Although the direct effects of the Pottinger ruling were limited,
In 2006, a panel of the Ninth Circuit resolved Jones v. City of Los Angeles and concluded that the defendants had not made an “informed choice” to sleep in public because of the lack of shelter availability.
In 2018, the Ninth Circuit again confronted the issue of homeless ordinances in Martin v. City of Boise.
The initial response to Jones and Martin was largely positive.
But academic commentators soon noticed the limitations of the Martin opinion. Professor Sara Rankin recently dismantled the Martin decision for simply giving the criminalization of homelessness a “makeover.”
According to Rankin, the Martin holding has accelerated the transcarceration of homeless individuals in three ways. First, cities such as Seattle have embraced “more frequent and less regulated encampment sweeps as a pipeline to confinement.”
Transcarceration efforts of these sorts are enabled by certain key limitations in the Martin opinion. For one thing, the Martin holding does not dictate any standards for the adequacy or beneficence of government-provided shelter before justifying criminalization. On the pure logic of the Martin opinion, even mass shelters in emergency tents suffice to transform urban camping from an inescapable incident of “status” to a voluntary “choice” for unsheltered homeless populations.
Rankin’s account of “transcarceration” aligns with how marginalized groups have historically been excluded, surveilled, and regulated within public spaces as a means of reinforcing existing social and status hierarchies. In her essay, Policing Marginality in Public Space, Professor Jamelia Morgan reveals how the policing of unsheltered individuals is part of a long history of criminal regulation of public spaces.
Morgan’s work highlights how constitutional protections that prohibit status crimes do little to prevent the overcriminalization of marginalized groups. Morgan specifically attacks the Martin decision as an example of inadequate constitutional rulemaking. Despite focusing on individual “choice” as a prerequisite for criminalization, the Martin court neglected to grapple with the social and cultural conditions that drive these choices.
Under the reasoning of cases like Jones and Martin, the availability of shelter beds is the dispositive issue in distinguishing between impermissibly punishing status and permissibly punishing voluntary conduct. Other courts have similarly pointed to the availability of shelter beds as a reason for dispensing with Eighth Amendment challenges to camping ordinances.
One of the more pernicious consequences of the Martin and Jones decisions is that the opinions shift the legal discourse about the criminalization of homelessness. Cities and states that have criminalized urban camping have typically done so unconditionally.
Martin and Jones shift this discourse by creating a narrative in which eschewing available shelter is a conscious “choice,” and therefore is a permissible target of criminal sanctions. Rather than grapple with the constitutionality of the law’s actual motivations, these opinions frame criminalization as a matter of punishing voluntary decisions by individuals experiencing homelessness.
By holding that criminal ordinances only punish the “status” of homelessness when shelter beds are unavailable, these decisions depict homelessness as a status that is escaped by a seemingly simple choice to seek shelter. The opinions never grapple with whether the compulsory requirement to use shelters, at the risk of criminal enforcement, is also a form of social punishment that targets homelessness as a status. The opinions make no effort to justify the imposition of criminal punishment on individuals who rationally choose not to utilize available shelter services.
III. The Choice to Use Shelters
One of the primary costs of centering temporary emergency shelters in the discourse about homelessness is that doing so tends to elide discussion about the deficiencies of many shelters. When shelters are valorized as an end goal of litigation or legislation—as with the right-to-shelter movements discussed above—they hold a revered place in the discourse that does not permit of nuance. They are held up broadly as the solution to the problem of homelessness, rather than as a temporary offering designed to alleviate the circumstances of some people some of the time. We see this cost most clearly in the judicial treatment of shelters under the Eighth Amendment. In concluding that urban camping laws no longer punish “status” when shelter services are available, courts have reified shelters as a one-size-fits-all solution to elevating individuals out of homelessness.
The reality is far less rosy. Estimates are that 77 percent of homeless individuals would prefer living unsheltered rather than occupying temporary emergency shelters provided by the state.
In this Section, I highlight these considerations to drive home a different point: respect for homeless individuals as persons ought to require us to defer to their intimate personal choices about how best to live their lives in the face of overwhelming constraints. This Section surveys just a few of the various considerations that individuals must weigh in deciding whether shelter services are appropriate for them. It does so to emphasize both the complexity and the intimacy of the choices that face individuals experiencing homelessness.
A. Physical Safety Considerations
One of the most central considerations for individuals deciding whether to use available shelter services is whether the shelter increases their physical safety. Life for unsheltered homeless individuals involves a considerable amount of interpersonal violence.
Violence within shelters is always a concern.
Apart from actual rates of violence, the perceived risk of physical violence may also deter many homeless individuals—especially women—from utilizing shelter services.
In early 2020, the coronavirus pandemic highlighted another way in which the traditional shelter structure threatens the physical health of residents. Coronavirus is a respiratory virus that spreads from infected persons to healthy ones through the accumulation of airborne droplets in enclosed spaces.
Throughout the year, coronavirus rapidly spread within shelters. Estimated transmission rates were upwards of 67 percent.
Coronavirus provides a poignant example of a broader point. Crowded shelters dramatically increase the transmission risk of many common diseases.
B. Accessibility Considerations
Many shelters also have barriers to use that complicate the decision of whether an individual might benefit from them. For those with mental and physical disabilities, shelters are often intolerable, if not outright inaccessible. Shelter buildings frequently lack basic accessibility accommodations required under federal law—such as ramps, elevators, handrails, and automatic doors.
Shelters may be similarly inaccessible to those with mental health and substance abuse issues. An estimated 21 percent of homeless individuals have a severe mental health condition, and an estimated 17 percent have a chronic substance abuse disorder.
C. Personal Property Considerations
Property loss is another key consideration for individuals deciding whether to utilize shelter services. For individuals experiencing homelessness, the accumulation and retention of personal property is a constant struggle.
The typical shelter model prevents people from bringing these possessions into the shelter.
Individuals deciding whether to use shelter services must often weigh the value of lost property against the value of a roof for a night. Because many shelters operate on a night-by-night model, a consistent bed in a shelter is not always guaranteed.
Homelessness takes a variety of forms, and so the kinds of property that individuals accumulate also can take many forms.
Even if a person decides to take a shelter bed, theft is unfortunately rampant. One formerly homeless individual described how stories of shoe theft kept him from using shelter services for a long time.
D. Interpersonal Considerations
Another significant, but often overlooked, consideration for those considering whether to use available shelters is the loss of interpersonal connections.
But as these social bonds form and flourish, the connections grow beyond the expediency of physical safety to create something akin to a family.
By contrast, shelters do not tend to be long-term spaces for people, which means that individual residents have little control over who they see and how often.
Romantic relationships also frequently inform the choice of whether to utilize shelter services.
Many homeless couples thus prefer to sleep on the streets rather than to separate their family.
Shelter policies can also separate homeless parents from their children.
Even when a parent is not separated from their child, parenting inside homeless shelters carries its own array of obstacles that might make staying in a shelter unappealing and impracticable. In one study, participants with infant children and toddlers reported that living in an emergency shelter negatively impacted their children in a number of ways, including causing “confusion, sadness, anxiety or depression, withdrawal, altered relationships with food, aggression, disregard for authority, and developmental regressions.”
Make no mistake, the use of government-run or government-funded shelter services is the right decision for some individuals some of the time. What this Part endeavors to show is not that these shelter services are universally insufficient. Rather, it highlights that they are not the universal, one-size-fits-all solution to homelessness that they are sometimes portrayed as. By centering shelter services in the political and legal discourses surrounding homelessness, both the right-to-shelter efforts of previous generations and the recent constitutional rulings of the Ninth Circuit have elided the complicated set of trade-offs entailed in individual decisions about how best to seek shelter while homeless. Ultimately, the choice between using available shelter services and self-sheltering is intimate, highly contextual, and deeply personal—an expression of one’s autonomous decision-making as a free individual.
IV. What Dignity Demands
What if homeless advocates have been misperceiving the right to shelter? If government-funded shelter services are not a universal solution for homeless individuals, perhaps it is time to consider an alternative conception of the right to shelter—the right to shelter as a negative right. Such a right would protect the decision of homeless individuals to undertake self-sheltering activities—from the simple use of blankets or bedding to the erection of temporary encampments in public spaces—free from the threat of criminalization. A negative right to shelter would ensure that homeless individuals have the freedom to choose where and how to find shelter, to protect themselves and their property, and to build meaningful connections with others.
Because it is founded on respect for the right of the individual to a specific form of self-determination, a negative right to shelter is perhaps most at home as an outgrowth of the right to human dignity guaranteed by the U.S. Constitution’s due process clauses.
The dignity guaranteed by substantive due process is best understood as ensuring a specific capacity for self-determination, particularly with respect to bodily autonomy and interpersonal relationships, and as opposed to the subordinating effects of criminalization. This Part outlines the due process dimensions of constitutional dignity and examines their implications for individuals experiencing homelessness. It begins with a reexamination of the 2003 decision in Lawrence v. Texas,
A. Dignity as Due Process
Nearly twenty years later, it can be easy to forget just how revolutionary the Supreme Court’s decision in Lawrence was. Consensual sodomy was criminalized in thirteen states.
By now, the facts are well-understood. John Geddes Lawrence, an older White man, was arrested along with Tyron Garner, a younger Black man, for engaging in consensual sodomy in Lawrence’s Texas apartment.
Court watchers at the time predicted a narrow decision. If the defendants should win, the majority opinion was expected to vindicate a formal equality guaranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause.
An alternative outcome—less likely, but still plausible—was that the Lawrence Court would vindicate the privacy interest in sexual activity behind closed doors. Drawing from decisions like Griswold v. Connecticut and Eisenstadt v. Baird, the defendants had argued that governments ought not be policing private bedrooms for evidence of deviant sex.
Writing for five members of the Court, however, Justice Kennedy eschewed these narrow grounds in favor of a broader opinion grounding sexual freedom in a robust account of liberty, autonomy, and, ultimately, human dignity. The first paragraph of the opinion opens expansively: “Liberty presumes an autonomy of self that includes freedom of thought, belief, expression, and certain intimate conduct. The instant case involves liberty of the person both in its spatial and in its more transcendent dimensions.”
The petitioners are entitled to respect for their private lives. The State cannot demean their existence or control their destiny by making their private sexual conduct a crime. Their right to liberty under the Due Process Clause gives them the full right to engage in their conduct without intervention of the government.
Together, these paragraphs establish the contours of the twin pillars upon which the Lawrence decision primarily rests: respecting a robust version of individual autonomy (controlling one’s destiny) and denouncing group subordination (not demeaning one’s existence). The lesson from Lawrence’s discussion of autonomy is that human dignity demands a certain capacity to direct the course of one’s life. The right to engage in relationships free from state interference is an artifact of a broader entitlement to something like self-government.
Between those two passages, the Court was surprisingly vague about whether the conduct at issue was a “fundamental right”—though the Court used the word “fundamental” no less than eight times in the majority opinion.
But the Court’s prolonged exploration of the “transcendent” dimensions of due process should leave no doubt that it was articulating the contours of a fundamental right. As Professor Larry Tribe observed in Lawrence’s immediate wake, Justice Kennedy took a novel approach to defining the right at issue. Rather than seek a historical grounding for the particular practice that the defendants had engaged in—the approach taken by the Bowers Court years earlier
It treated the substantive due process precedents invoked by one side or the other not as a record of the inclusion of various activities in—and the exclusion of other activities from—a fixed list defined by tradition, but as reflections of a deeper pattern involving the allocation of decision-making roles, not always fully understood at the time each precedent was added to the array.
The fundamental right articulated by Lawrence is grounded in a respect for individual self-definition or self-governance and centered on intimate personal choices. This right, though framed by reference to the Constitution’s invocation of “liberty,” more closely tracks contemporary definitions of human dignity. For example, Professor Gregory Alexander defines human dignity as “both a potential for autonomy [conceived of as self-authorship] and a right to develop that potential.”
Lawrence’s version of this self-definition right had two further essential features. First, Justice Kennedy took pains to emphasize the role of interpersonal relationships in providing meaning to life.
Second, Lawrence’s origins are grounded in Supreme Court opinions that emphasize the intimacy of personal decisions broadly protecting bodily autonomy. Consider Griswold v. Connecticut, the seminal Supreme Court case striking down Connecticut’s law outlawing the use of contraception,
The strongest connection to human dignity in the Lawrence opinion, however, comes not from the Court’s embrace of a self-definition right, but from its recognition that the criminal law is frequently used to subordinate unpopular social groups. In eschewing the more formalistic and technocratic Equal Protection analysis advanced by Justice O’Connor’s concurrence, Justice Kennedy argued that the Court must not leave unexamined the denigrating social stigma of criminalization, even where the law technically extends universally.
The dignity analysis of Lawrence thus casts inequality concerns as a matter of substantive subordination, rather than formal equality.
This intermingling of both substantive liberty—liberty as self-definition—and substantive equality—equality as anti-subordination—defines what Professor Tribe has coined as the Supreme Court’s jurisprudence of “equal dignity.”
Lawrence, more than any other decision in the Supreme Court’s history, both presupposed and advanced an explicitly equality-based and relationally situated theory of substantive liberty. The “liberty” of which the Court spoke was as much about equal dignity and respect as it was about freedom of action—more so, in fact.
To be clear, Lawrence’s conception of dignity as due process is not exclusively an invention of Justice Kennedy’s jurisprudence. Dating back to 1923, the Supreme Court has frequently blurred the formalist distinctions between equality and liberty in its analysis of substantive due process, rendering decisions that, with the benefit of hindsight, should be best understood as sounding in the sort of dignity that Lawrence makes central.
Nor does it stop with Lawrence. That decision is the focus of this Section because it provides particularly analogous tools for the dismantling of criminalization based on social status. But the Supreme Court has since extended its dignity jurisprudence, and its more recent cases are instructive for understanding the scope of the principles at play. In United States v. Windsor, the Court relied on the principle of human dignity in striking down a key provision of the Defense of Marriage Act (DOMA).
Windsor explained that dignity can be conferred—and, by implication, denied—by the government’s provision of statutory rights. The Court claimed that providing the right to marry to cross-sex couples “enhanced the recognition, dignity, and protection of the class in their own community.”
Obergefell’s depiction of dignity emphasized the anti-subordination dimensions of due process introduced in Lawrence and extended in Windsor. The Obergefell Court explained that the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment protected “fundamental liberties,” including “certain personal choices central to individual dignity and autonomy.”
Given this history, it may be tempting to see the Supreme Court’s dignity jurisprudence as exclusively about the stages of political legitimization for those who identify as LGBTQIA+. Lawrence decriminalized same-sex sodomy, Windsor undermined DOMA, and Obergefell extended the privilege of marriage to all. Even Masterpiece Cakeshop, Ltd. v. Colorado Civil Rights Commission involved Justice Kennedy invoking dignity as a means to recognize the “community-wide stigma” that might affect gay couples who are denied services.
But there are strong reasons to believe that dignity extends beyond this narrow context. For one, consider the pains that the Lawrence majority took to reframe the nature of the rights claim. Bowers v. Hardwick had seemingly resolved the constitutionality of same-sex sodomy laws less than two decades prior to Lawrence. It had done so by denying that the Constitution “confers a fundamental right upon homosexuals to engage in sodomy.”
Nor are Lawrence’s predecessors limited to cases exclusively focusing on sexual intimacy and its consequences. As Justice Souter observed in his concurring opinion in Washington v. Glucksberg, “[e]very human being of adult years and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be done with his own body.”
Lawrence itself then shifts this narrower discussion of bodily integrity into a broader principle of interpersonal associative freedoms. In Lawrence, the Court emphasized that the physical act of sexual intercourse is “but one element in a personal bond that is more enduring.”
In sum, the Lawrence decision recast constitutional “liberty” as something more than a narrow right to sexual autonomy. The dignitary dimensions of the decision both cabin and contextualize the rights claim at issue, which allows the case to serve as a touchstone for future interpretations of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments. At its core, Lawrence counsels in favor of decriminalization when laws burden intimate personal decisions that implicate fundamental interests in bodily integrity and interpersonal relationships, including familial relationships. Further, Lawrence demonstrates the sensitivity of due process analysis to the role that criminalization plays in subordinating populations. When the criminal law operates to stigmatize and subordinate a group defined by its intimate personal choices about how best to craft a life worthy of meaning, substantive due process stands as a bulwark against the tyranny of the majority.
Last term, however, in Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization,
Nevertheless, the Dobbs decision formally leaves Lawrence undisturbed.
B. The Dignity in Self-Sheltering
Like the right to make choices about one’s sexual relationships, the ability to make autonomous choices about how best to navigate periods of housing instability protects and promotes essential human dignity. As the previous Section illustrated, the form of dignity protected by constitutional due process is intimately connected to notions of self-definition and self-governance. It is principally concerned with respecting the most intimate choices of an individual, regardless of that individual’s membership in a disfavored social group.
Laws criminalizing urban camping threaten a homeless individual’s interest in bodily integrity and intimate associations by dictating the outcome of one of the most intimate decisions that a homeless individual must make—when and whether to utilize available shelter services. The choice of where to shelter is a sensitive, key decision central to one’s existence, family life, community welfare, and their development of human personality. Urban camping laws take away from homeless individuals the freedom to make the decision—based upon their values, their assessment of their self-interest, and their personal relationships with others—about where best to build a life under extreme constraints. Absent some exceptional need, the state ought not to interfere in this personal and important decision about individuals’ private lives.
State regulation of urban camping implicates the well-recognized liberty interest in bodily integrity.
Moreover, the Supreme Court’s substantive due process jurisprudence has recognized that “choices to enter into and maintain certain intimate human relationships must be secured against undue intrusion by the State because of the role of such relationships in safeguarding the individual freedom that is central to our constitutional scheme.”
Existing urban camping ordinances place homeless individuals in a double bind. Either the individual must subject themself to shelter services that may negatively impact their physical well-being, property rights, and established community ties, or the individual must risk criminal sanctions for choosing to construct a life unsheltered. Bodily health, property, and community are not merely isolated considerations, though essential in their own right, but combine to reflect the “rational continuum” of liberty ensured by the Constitution.
In arriving at the correct constitutional balance, we must also remember that criminal law both stigmatizes and subordinates. Cities and states with urban camping prohibitions are enforcing their preference for shelter services using the full power of the criminal law. Individuals who are caught self-sheltering are subject to arrest and incarceration, loss of property, and separation from their community. The social stigma against homeless individuals is cemented by laws and ordinances that denounce as “criminal” behaviors that are essential to survival in desperate circumstances.
The depiction of dignity that emerges from the Supreme Court’s recent Due Process jurisprudence contains a strong antisubordination norm. Professor Reva Siegel has noted that “the case law is rich with diverse expressions of antisubordination values.”
By casting self-sheltering activities as criminal, the state automatically brands homeless individuals, and their attempts to craft some meaningful existence out of a deeply unequal situation, as inferior to those who build meaning within the structures of established privilege. Criminalization creates a lens through which the social denigration of the indigent can be legitimately channeled. People of means need not attempt to justify condemning poverty if they are free to condemn criminal activities, such as camping, loitering, urinating, or begging—activities that they are able to psychologically distance themselves from by dint of their own circumstances.
Troublingly, criminalization is animated by social stigma grounded in inaccurate characterizations of poverty and vagrancy. Like homosexuality, homelessness has long been targeted by criminal laws that are motivated by moral condemnation and denigration, rather than public safety. The earliest laws against “vagrancy” targeted characteristics, rather than conduct.
One of the things that Lawrence makes clear is that the criminalization of homelessness cannot be insulated from scrutiny by the glib observation that such laws apply “equally” to the housed and unhoused alike. Had such an approach been endorsed in Lawrence, Texas would have been able to preserve its sodomy laws by modifying them to also reach opposite-sex participants. That result would have ignored the targeted discrimination and stigmatization that, at least partially, animated Justice Kennedy’s substantive due process analysis.
A popular interpretation of Lawrence, however, posits that the Court subtextually relied on something like the classic principle of desuetude. This is the version of Lawrence advocated by Professor Cass Sunstein.
One of the central concerns of a desuetude interpretation of Lawrence is that it substantially narrows the future applications of the liberty principles the case announced. To some—like Sunstein—this is a virtue.
On this view, the moral grounding of laws prohibiting urban camping becomes a fundamental inquiry. To be sure, such laws are currently popular with legislatures. Homeless advocacy organizations that track the proliferation of criminal prohibitions have consistently found that the number of such laws has increased over the past decade.
Thus, even on a desuetude view of Lawrence, one may plausibly question the defensibility of criminalizing essential activities like urban camping. We know that urban camping ordinances are inconsistently enforced. In practice, the criminal sanction frequently operates as a background threat, inducing compliance with simple orders to “move along.”
One common rejoinder to the rights claim that I am making is that Lawrence’s own conception of liberty was explicitly confined to private spaces. Articulating a list of potential exceptions to the sexual liberty just established, Justice Kennedy included the fact that Lawrence did not involve “public conduct.”
The answer to this rejoinder can be found in assessing the state’s justifications for interfering with personal liberty. We must begin by accepting, as Lawrence dictates, that personal autonomy is a right of such importance that it implicates not only sexual decision-making, but also fundamental questions about the mysteries of human life.
No similar potential for causing third-party harm derives from urban camping—from merely existing in public spaces. As discussed, the best understanding of laws against urban camping is that they exist to remove unimaginable poverty from public view, either by coercing homeless individuals into shelters or by empowering police to physically remove them from streets.
An alternative justification that is occasionally offered in support of urban camping ordinances is that homeless individuals unfairly convert shared public spaces. A homeless encampment, the charge goes, transforms a parcel of public land into an effectively private one, available solely for the use and enjoyment of its occupants. Although there is some logic to this claim, public spaces exist to be occupied, and homeless individuals are no less a part of the “public” to whom these spaces are dedicated than anyone else. By definition, physical spaces occupied by any member of the public cannot be simultaneously occupied by others. Many accepted everyday activities “convert” public spaces in this way: setting up chairs and shade at a beach, spreading out a blanket in the park, etc.
The true concern is not that homeless individuals are occupying public spaces—it is that they are putting public spaces to undesirable uses. Consider laws against “loitering.” Typically defined as remaining in a particular public place without a “lawful purpose,” loitering laws preclude homeless individuals from existing in public spaces for prolonged periods.
Or take, for example, my own personal experience with homelessness that opened this Article. Under the relevant city ordinance, sleeping in a vehicle parked on a public residential street is defined as an illegal “use” of a vehicle for dwelling.
If I am correct about the essential liberty interest involved in deciding to camp in public, then much more is needed from the state’s justifications. A bare majoritarian desire to remove poverty from public view is insufficient. Arguments about allocating scarce public resources are unsubstantiated. In truth, the criminalization of urban camping is driven by the voting majority’s negative attitudes toward homelessness, including disgust, discomfort, and condemnation.
C. The Scope of Decriminalization
Decriminalization is not without its limits. Even if urban camping ordinances are held unconstitutional for impinging upon the dignity of individuals experiencing homelessness, the state retains a plethora of options for regulating visible homelessness, which I would expect to be the next frontier of legal challenges. This Section examines three such options, each of which I believe would be likely to withstand constitutional scrutiny. The first option is zoning. If cities are no longer permitted to respond to urban camping with blanket criminalization, they may nevertheless be able to control the spaces in which visible homelessness exists through the reasonable exercise of zoning powers. Second, cities may retain the power to criminalize harm-causing behaviors by individuals experiencing homelessness. A lynchpin of the argument for decriminalizing urban camping is that the laws serve insufficiently substantial government interests because the behavior causes no third-party harms. Decriminalization therefore likely fails to extend to conduct, such as violent crime, drug use, and arguably public urination or defecation, which all have a claim to third-party harms.
Zoning has been a foundational power of local governments for roughly a century.
In 1977, the Supreme Court declared that the power of local governments to zone may not trample upon fundamental due process rights. In Moore v. City of East Cleveland, the Court held that an East Cleveland housing ordinance violated the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment when it purported to limit dwelling occupancy to members of a single, nuclear family.
In a now-famous concurring opinion,
Despite Moore’s affirmation that cities may not use zoning to deny individuals certain fundamental rights, courts have upheld as reasonable zoning schemes that merely incidentally burden such rights.
Consequently, cities will likely retain the power to regulate the location of public homeless encampments within their borders, notwithstanding a fundamental right to self-shelter. To date, a handful of cities have already experimented with establishing specifically designated zones for homeless residents.
While zoning of this sort may be legally permissible, it primarily functions to concentrate and obscure extreme poverty, which can be damaging to the individuals subjected to it.
Beyond zoning, cities and states will likely also retain the ability to criminalize behaviors attendant to homelessness to the extent that those behaviors cause third-party harms. Laws against vagrancy and urban camping have long been justified as prophylactic measures designed to empower police to prevent more serious crimes.
Under the Supreme Court’s well-established framework, even fundamental rights must bend to accommodate narrowly tailored laws that serve compelling state interests.
A more interesting question arises with respect to conduct that engenders substantial disdain or disgust, but that less obviously harms third parties. Here, I am thinking particularly of public urination and defecation, along with public sex. Unlike other forms of crime among the unsheltered homeless, these activities may be thought of as intimately connected to the protected conduct of self-sheltering. Moreover, a robust theory of dignity grounded in moral philosophy would likely view such conduct as an inescapable component of public existence.
As noted earlier, there are at least nontrivial arguments for keeping human nudity and certain bodily activities from non-consenting viewers.
Those who fear that the decriminalization of urban camping will necessitate tolerating increased crimes of violence, drug use, or acts of public indecency can therefore rest easy.
Lastly, and perhaps most troublingly, recognizing a negative right to shelter likely leaves unaffected the government’s power to sweep, deconstruct, or relocate homeless encampments in furtherance of health and sanitation goals. Sweeps of this nature have long been part of communities’ responses to the creation of homeless encampments.
Encampment sweeps motivated by these concerns are civil, rather than criminal, undertakings.
While there are specific quirks for each municipality, the general process is largely the same. A notice is posted nearby with an allotted time frame, usually three days or so, during which people need to vacate the area. (Sometimes notices don’t appear at all.) At some point after that time elapses (if it’s raining or if there is a protest, the sweep may be delayed a few days), a combination of police officers and sanitation workers invade. Police escort those living in the tents away, and may fence off the area. Once the area is “secure,” sanitation workers begin throwing everything into the idling garbage truck.
While they still must comport with the dictates of due process,
To be sure, the effects of encampment sweeps can be truly devastating to those individuals affected.
But there are also real health and safety concerns at the heart of many sweeps. When these interests genuinely motivate encampment sweeps—rather than pretextually provide cover for sweeps in service of other interests, such as aesthetic concerns or housed citizen satisfaction
Conclusion
For over forty years, advocates have responded to the criminalization of homelessness by calling for a “right to shelter.” But these calls have been about the wrong right to shelter. Attempts to frame shelter as a positive right—an enforceable entitlement to have the government provide or fund a temporary shelter bed for every homeless individual—have largely floundered. Moreover, the prominence of this right-to-shelter rhetoric in the discourse surrounding homelessness has had pernicious consequences, eliding weaknesses in shelter offerings and reifying temporary emergency offerings as the solution to a truly intractable problem.
This Article takes a different tack. It has articulated and defended a negative right to shelter as a fundamental right to shelter oneself free from government interference, especially criminalization. This new right to shelter emerges from our constitutional due process jurisprudence premised on maintaining and defending human dignity. To be clear, I have little hope that the Supreme Court, as currently constituted, would have an appetite for recognizing a negative right to shelter. But I think that a faithful adherence to existing precedent—and, in particular, to the potential for Lawrence v. Texas to have applications beyond the realms of sex and sexuality—reveals a path to identifying such a negative right that may hold sway in lower courts. Substantive due process has long protected the human capacity for self-determination while rejecting group-based subordination enshrined through criminalization.
Respect for homeless individuals as persons ought to require us to defer to their intimate personal choices about how best to live life in the face of overwhelming constraints. This means learning to confront, rather than hide, the realities of visible poverty. It means protecting the decisions of those homeless individuals who rationally prefer to undertake self-sheltering activities—from the use of blankets or bedding to the erection of temporary encampments in public spaces—from the threat of criminalization. True decriminalization would ensure that homeless individuals have the freedom to choose where and how to find shelter, to protect themselves and their property, and to build meaningful connections with one another.
- Among other things, I had the social privileges of a cisgender, heterosexual, White male. For information on the role of race, gender, and sexuality in the experience of homeless youths, see Jama Shelton, Jonah DeChants, Kim Bender, Hsun-Ta Hsu, Diane Santa Maria, Robin Petering, Kristin Ferguson, Sarah Narendorf & Anamika Barman-Adhikari, Homelessness and Housing Experiences Among LGBTQ Young Adults in Seven U.S. Cities, 20 Cityscape 9 (2018). ↑
- Studies have consistently found high rates of victimization among homeless adolescents—more often physical abuse for males and sexual abuse for females. See Angela J. Stewart, Mandy Steiman, Ana Mari Cauce, Bryan N. Cochran, Les B. Whitbeck & Dan R. Hoyt, Victimization and Posttraumatic Stress Disorder Among Homeless Adolescents, 43 J. Am. Acad. Child & Adolescent Psychiatry 325, 329 (2004). Homeless youths report high rates of hypervigilance and avoidance as strategies to reduce the risks of victimization, likely at the expense of long-term psychological and emotional health. See id. at 329–30. ↑
- Individuals experiencing homelessness frequently must carry all their belongings with them, a burden that can impede their sense of autonomy and even hinder their ability to find work. See, e.g., Zarina Khairzada, This Backpack Isn’t for Sale, but It’s Helping the Homeless, Spectrum News 1 (Aug. 16, 2019), https://spectrumnews1.com/ca/la-west/news/2019/08/15/this-backpack-isn-t-for-sale--but-it-s-helping-the-homeless [https://perma.cc/VY62-C9QP]. Even something as simple as a high-quality backpack “makes a difference and this creates a sense of dignity, a sense of safety.” Id. (internal quotation omitted). ↑
- E.C. Hedberg & Bill Hart, A New Look: A Survey of Arizona’s Homeless Population 7–9 (2013), https://morrisoninstitute.asu.edu/sites/default/files/newlook-homelesssurvey.pdf [https://perma.cc/MW7N-KUNC]. ↑
- Despite popular perceptions of homelessness as a chronic and persistent condition, the more common experience is for individuals to experience homelessness in brief, transitional episodes. See Adam M. Lippert & Barrett A. Lee, Stress, Coping, and Mental Health Differences Among Homeless People, 85 Socio. Inquiry 343, 345 (2015). A 2017 report from the U.S. Department of Housing and Urban Development found that only about 24 percent of individuals experiencing homelessness nationally had chronic patterns of homelessness. Meghan Henry, Ryan Watt, Lily Rosenthal & Azim Shivji, U.S. Dep’t of Hous. & Urb. Dev., The 2017 Annual Homeless Assessment Report to Congress 62 (2017), https://www.huduser.gov/portal/sites/default/files/pdf/2017-AHAR-Part-1.pdf [https://perma.cc/2PQU-H4S9]. ↑
- Phoenix Community Action Response Engagement Services (CARES) statistics indicate that nearly 75 percent of people refused services when contacted. See Jessica Boehm, Phoenix Residents Reported 1,500 Homeless Encampments. See Where They Are, AZ Central (May 7, 2019), https://www.azcentral.com/story/news/local/phoenix/2019/05/06/phoenix-homelessness-increase-reported-encampments-community-services/3410072002/ [https://perma.cc/J3AJ-3EHP]. ↑
- See generally Sara K. Rankin, Punishing Homelessness, 22 New Crim. L. Rev. 99, 110 (2019) (“Bans on sleeping in vehicles—the thin tin line that separates a human being from the street—increased by a staggering 143% nationwide since 2006.”) (citing Tristia Bauman, Janet Hostetler, Janelle Fernandez, Eric Tars, Michael Santos, Jenifer Brewer, Elizabeth Dennis, Ruth El & Maria Foscarinis, Housing Not Handcuffs: Ending the Criminalization of Homelessness in U.S. Cities 11 (2018), https://web.archive.org/web/20190331135117/https://nlchp.org//wp-content/uploads/2018/10/Housing-Not-Handcuffs.pdf). ↑
- Boehm, supra note 6. ↑
- Ben A. McJunkin, Homelessness, Indignity, and the Promise of Mandatory Citations for Urban Camping, 52 Ariz. St. L.J. 955, 955 (2020) (noting that typical laws criminalizing homelessness include “loitering in parks, resting at bus stops, obstructing sidewalks, pitching tents, asking for money, asking for work, and sleeping just about anywhere”). ↑
- See, e.g., Phx., Ariz. City Code § 23-30(B) (defining “camping” to include “sleeping activities, or making preparations to sleep, including the laying down of bedding for the purpose of sleeping, or storing personal belongings”). ↑
- See, e.g., id. § 23-30(A). ↑
- See, e.g., id. § 23-30(B). ↑
- See Rankin, supra note 7, at 102 (“Key drivers for the criminalization of homelessness are increasingly popular laws and policies that seek to expel visibly poor people from public space.”). ↑
- See Matt Tinoco, It’s (Still) Against the Law to Sleep in Your Car in LA, LAist (Aug. 1, 2019), https://laist.com/news/los-angeles-homeless-sleeping-car-rv [https://perma.cc/W6KD-5FZV]. ↑
- See id. (“The fine for sleeping in your car in an off-limits zone starts at $25 for first-time offenders.”). ↑
- See generally Alexandra Natapoff, Misdemeanors, 85 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1313, 1313 (2012) (“The consequences of these convictions are significant: in addition to the stigma of a criminal record, misdemeanants are often heavily fined or incarcerated, and can lose jobs, housing, or education opportunities.”). ↑
- Rankin, supra note 7, at 108 (“Once individuals are saddled with a misdemeanor or a warrant, they are often rendered ineligible to access shelter, food, services, and other benefits that might support their ability to emerge from homelessness.”). ↑
- See Judith Scott-Clayton, Thinking “Beyond the Box”: The Use of Criminal Records in College Admissions, Brookings (Sept. 28, 2017), https://www.brookings.edu/research/thinking-beyond-the-box-the-use-of-criminal-records-in-college-admissions/ [https://perma.cc/D2FF-3ZZ7] (“Three national surveys of institutional admissions practices, conducted in 2009, 2010, and 2014 by separate research teams, indicate that 60 to 80 percent of private institutions and 55 percent of public institutions require undergraduate applicants to answer criminal history questions as part of the admissions process.”). ↑
- See, e.g., Applying with a Criminal Record, Yale L. Sch., https://law.yale.edu/centers-workshops/law-school-access-program/applying-criminal-record [https://perma.cc/XVN9-8CNP]. ↑
- See infra Part II. ↑
- The distinction between “positive” and “negative” rights is generally traced to Isaiah Berlin’s seminal lecture, Two Concepts of Liberty (1958), reprinted in The Proper Study of Mankind: An Anthology of Essays 191, 194 (Henry Hardy & Roger Hausheer eds., 1997). “Positive” rights are typically portrayed as those requiring affirmative action to fulfill a specific entitlement—for example, they may best be characterized as a right to something, rather than a right to the be free from something. See generally Positive and Negative Liberty, Stan. Encyclopedia of Phil. (Nov. 19, 2021), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/liberty-positive-negative [https://perma.cc/7WHW-A9S4]. ↑
- See infra Part II.A–B. ↑
- Martin v. City of Boise, 902 F.3d 1031, 1035 (9th Cir. 2018), amended by 920 F.3d 584 (9th Cir. 2019) (en banc). ↑
- See infra Part II.C. ↑
- See Cameron Baskett, Note, Cruel and Unusual Camping, 109 Ky. L.J. 593, 604 (2020) (describing how proposals to construct “large, centralized facilities that are available to the homeless twenty-four hours a day” would undercut the impact of the Martin decision). ↑
- See infra Part IV. ↑
- Although the word “dignity” does not appear in the due process clauses of either the Fifth or Fourteenth Amendments, much of the Supreme Court’s due process jurisprudence over the past half-decade has identified human dignity as a core value protected by those clauses. See infra Part IV.A. ↑
- See infra Part IV.A. ↑
- See infra Part II.C. ↑
- Meghan Henry, Tanya de Sousa, Caroline Roddey, Swati Gayen & Thomas Joe Bednar, U.S. Dep’t of Hous. & Urb. Dev., The 2020 Annual Homeless Assessment Report (AHAR) to Congress 6 (Jan. 2021), https://www.huduser.gov/portal/sites/default/files/pdf/2020-AHAR-Part-1.pdf [https://perma.cc/Y2T6-YQ8E] [hereinafter HUD 2020 AHAR]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Nat’l All. to End Homelessness, Faith-Based Organizations: Fundamental Partners in Ending Homelessness 2 (May 2017), http://endhomelessness.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/06/05-04-2017_Faith-Based.pdf [https://perma.cc/3VKN-AGKN] (“In 2016, as a conservative estimate, faith-based organizations provided over 41 percent of the emergency shelter beds for single adults and nearly 16 percent of beds for families.”). ↑
- HUD 2020 AHAR, supra note 30, at 8. ↑
- See HUD 2020 AHAR, supra note 30, at 6 (providing point-in-time estimates of 391,440 sheltered and 173,268 unsheltered individuals in 2015, compared to 354,386 sheltered and 226,080 unsheltered individuals in 2020). ↑
- Darrell Stanley, Maria Foscarinis & Jennifer Wang, Don’t Count on It: How the HUD Point‑in‑Time Count Underestimates the Homelessness Crisis in America 28 (2017), https://nlchp.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/10/HUD-PIT-report2017.pdf [https://perma.cc/KTK6-WVSH]. Point-in-time counts are administered by the U.S. Department of Housing and Urban Development through its Continuum of Care (COC) programs, which counts sheltered and unsheltered homeless individuals at a “point-in-time”—typically a day. Id. at 8, 10. The point-in-time, or the length of the count, varies, however. While most COCs conduct the count in a single night, some conduct it over several. Id. at 10. ↑
- See Stephen Metraux, Dennis Culhane, Stacy Raphael, Matthew White, Carol Pearson, Eric Hirsch, Patricia Ferrell, Steve Rice, Barbara Ritter & Stephen J. Cleghorn, Assessing Homeless Population Size Through the Use of Emergency and Transitional Shelter Services in 1998: Results from the Analysis of Administrative Data from Nine U.S. Jurisdictions, 116 Pub. Health Reps. 344, 344 (2001) (finding that the annual number of homeless individuals is 2.5 to 10.2 times greater than can be obtained using a point-in-time count). Estimating the number of individuals who experience homelessness annually has proven challenging because homelessness is typically temporary and cyclical. See Lippert & Lee, supra note 5, at 345. The most-commonly cited estimate of homelessness is the Department of Housing and Urban Development’s Point-in-Time Count, which captures only visible homelessness on a single (or a couple) night(s) of the year. See Lillian Kilduff & Beth Jarosz, How Many People in the United States Are Experiencing Homelessness?, PRB (Sept. 22, 2020), https://www.prb.org/resources/how-many-people-in-the-united-states-are-experiencing-homelessness [https://perma.cc/RD4A-PLJB]. ↑
- Researchers have found that about 6 percent of a studied population from the Baby Boomer demographic experienced homelessness in their lifetime. See Vincent A. Fusaro, Helen G. Levy & Luke H. Shaefer, Racial and Ethnic Disparities in the Lifetime Prevalence of Homelessness in the United States, 55 Demography 2119, 2123 (2018) (finding that approximately 6.2 percent of Baby Boomer adults have experienced at least a single spell of homelessness). If that rate holds across populations, then roughly 20.4 million living Americans should be expected to experience homelessness at least once in their lifetimes. ↑
- See The Gap: A Shortage of Affordable Rental Homes, Nat’l Low Income Hous. Coal., https://reports.nlihc.org/gap/about [https://perma.cc/Q3HE-42LV]. ↑
- Abha Bhattarai, Chris Alcantara & Andrew Van Dam, Rents Are Rising Everywhere. See How Much Prices Are up in Your Area, Wash. Post (Apr. 21, 2022), https://www.washingtonpost.com/business/interactive/2022/rising-rent-prices/ [https://perma.cc/845S-JNYS]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- The COVID-19 pandemic in 2020 has made this reality evident. An estimated twenty to forty million workers lost their jobs as business shut down or paused. See Eric Morath, How Many U.S. Workers Have Lost Jobs During the Coronavirus Pandemic? There Are Several Ways to Count, Wall St. J. (June 3, 2020), https://www.wsj.com/articles/how-many-u-s-workers-have-lost-jobs-during-coronavirus-pandemic-there-are-several-ways-to-count-11591176601 [https://perma.cc/9UGJ-DHGJ]. In 2020, federal and state governments passed temporary eviction moratoriums that restricted landlords from filing new eviction actions based on non-payment of rent. See, e.g., Coronavirus Aid, Relief, and Economic Security Act, H.R. 748, 116th Cong. (2020) (“CARES Act”), Sec. 4024; A.B. 3088 (Cal. 2020); New York Covid-19 Emergency Eviction and Foreclosure Prevention Act, S.B. 9114 (N.Y. 2020). As those moratoriums expired, millions of individuals were suddenly at risk of eviction. Michael Casey, ‘A Lot of People Will Be Displaced’: Tenants Prepare for End of Federal Eviction Moratorium, USA Today (July 31, 2021), https://www.usatoday.com/story/money/2021/07/31/millions-tenants-face-evictions-homelessness-federal-eviction-moratorium-ends/5442925001/ [https://perma.cc/VY8B-SC3Y]. Early estimates predicted that as many as forty million people could become homeless at the expiration of these moratoriums. See Marc Ramirez, Sarah Taddeo & Tiffany Cusaac-Smith, The Federal Eviction Moratorium Expires in January. It Could Leave 40 Million Americans Homeless, USA Today (Dec. 24, 2020), https://www.usatoday.com/story/news/nation/2020/12/24/
covid-eviction-moratoriums-could-eventually-leave-americans-homeless/4018226001/ [https://perma.cc/9YHE-VMBH]. ↑
- Andrew Aurand, Abby Cooper, Dan Emmanuel, Ikra Rafi & Diane Yentel, Out of Reach 2 (2019) (explaining that there is no metropolitan area in the country in which a minimum wage worker working forty hours per week can afford market rent for a two-bedroom apartment). ↑
- Veronica Harnish, I’ve Been Homeless 3 Times. The Problem Isn’t Drugs or Mental Illness—It’s Poverty, Vox (Mar. 8, 2016), https://www.vox.com/2016/3/8/11173304/homeless-in-america [https://perma.cc/DQ7B-6ENB]. ↑
- Tristia Bauman, Rajan Bal, Karianna Barr, Maria Foscarinis, Brandy Ryan, Eric Tars, Taylor de Laveaga, Joy Kim, Darren O’Connor & Scott Pease, Housing Not Handcuffs 2019: Ending the Criminalization of Homelessness in U.S. Cities 12–14 (2019), https://homelesslaw.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/12/HOUSING-NOT-HANDCUFFS-2019-FINAL.pdf [https://perma.cc/GDC3-3CA2] [hereinafter NLCHP, Housing Not Handcuffs]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- See, e.g., Rankin, supra note 7, at 122. ↑
- See, e.g., Chris Herring, Dilara Yarbrough & Lisa Marie Alatorre, Pervasive Penality: How the Criminalization of Poverty Perpetuates Homelessness, 67 Soc. Probs. 131, 137 (2020); Tony Robinson, No Right to Rest: Police Enforcement Patterns and Quality of Life Consequences of the Criminalization of Homelessness, 55 Urb. Affs. Rev. 41, 64 (2019). ↑
- McJunkin, supra note 9, at 962. ↑
- See, e.g., An Act for Suppressing and Punishing of Rogues, Vagabonds, Common Beggars, and Other Idle, Disorderly, and Lewd Persons, in The Perpetual Laws of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts 411 (2d ed., 1801) (1788), https://books.google.com/books?id=ADw4AAAAIAAJ [https://perma.cc/F6ZK-2SZK]. ↑
- Harry Simon, Towns Without Pity: A Constitutional and Historical Analysis of Official Efforts to Drive Homeless Persons from American Cities, 66 Tul. L. Rev. 631, 633–34 (1992). ↑
- See Forrest W. Lacey, Vagrancy and Other Crimes of Personal Condition, 66 Harv. L. Rev. 1203, 1208–09 (1953); see also Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville, 405 U.S. 156, 156 n.1 (1972) (providing an example of a city's vagrancy ordinance). ↑
- Jeffrey S. Adler, A Historical Analysis of the Law of Vagrancy, 27 Criminology 209, 215–16 (1989). The roots of American vagrancy legislation run all the way back to fifteenth century attempts at wage stabilization in England following the Black Death. See Caleb Foote, Vagrancy-Type Law and Its Administration, 104 U. Pa. L. Rev. 603, 615–16 (1956). However, the adoption and enforcement of vagrancy laws in America also reflects the country’s racist history. See Kelly Lytle Hernández, City of Inmates: Conquest, Rebellion, and the Rise of Human Caging in Los Angeles, 1771-1965, at 36 (2017) (explaining that nineteenth century municipal codes in California were primarily enforced against Indigenous populations). ↑
- See Lacey, supra note 51, at 1217 (“Though vagrancy statutes no longer have the aim of forcing the idle to work or reducing the cost of poor relief, they very definitely do retain their historic purpose as a method of preventing crime.”); Foote, supra note 52, at 614 (“Administratively, vagrancy-type statutes are regarded as essential criminal preventives, providing a residual police power to facilitate the arrest, investigation and incarceration of suspicious persons.”). ↑
- See Sara K. Rankin, The Influence of Exile, 76 Md. L. Rev. 4, 21–24 (2016) (discussing the contemporary stigmas that homelessness is self-inflicted and indicative of future criminality). ↑
- See McJunkin, supra note 9, at 970. ↑
- These narratives were even accepted legally. See, e.g., District of Columbia v. Hunt, 163 F.2d 833, 835 (D.C. Cir. 1947) (“A vagrant is a probable criminal; and the purpose of the statute is to prevent crimes which may likely flow from his mode of life.”); see generally William O. Douglas, Vagrancy and Arrest on Suspicion, 70 Yale. L.J. 1 (1960) (criticizing vagrancy laws for permitting arrests on mere suspicion of criminality). ↑
- Foote, supra note 52, at 614 (“[V]agrancy-type crime accounts for more than one third of all arrests tabulated in the Uniform Crime Reports.”). ↑
- See Debra A. Livingston, Police Discretion and the Quality of Life in Public Places: Courts, Communities, and the New Policing, 97 Colum. L. Rev. 551, 596 (1997). ↑
- Laura Weinrib, The Vagrancy Law Challenge and the Vagaries of Legal Change, 43 Law & Soc. Inquiry 1669, 1670 (2018). ↑
- 405 U.S. 156, 162 (1972). ↑
- Id. at 163. ↑
- Id. at 164. ↑
- Id. at 170. It is worth noting that four of the Papachristou defendants contended that their arrest was motivated by their racial composition—Black men driving in a car with White women. See Petitioner’s Brief at 5–7, Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville, 405 U.S. 156 (1972) (No. 70-5030), 1971 WL 133167. ↑
- See, e.g., Maria Foscarinis, Homelessness in America: A Human Rights Crisis, 13 J.L. Soc’y 515, 515–16 (2012) (explaining that rising homelessness in the early 1980s “resulted in the emergence of homelessness as a serious national crisis affecting a broad range of the population and the country”). ↑
- Id.; Nat’l Acads. of Scis., Eng’g, & Med., Permanent Supporting Housing: Evaluating the Evidence for Improving Health Outcomes Among People Experiencing Chronic Homelessness 175–76, 178 (2018) [hereinafter The History of Homelessness in the United States]. ↑
- *The History of Homelessness in the United States, supra* note 65, at 176 (internal citation omitted). ↑
- How Many People Experience Homelessness?, Nat’l Coal. for the Homeless (July 2009) (internal citation omitted), https://www.nationalhomeless.org/factsheets/How_Many.html [https://perma.cc/BQQ3-YACW]. ↑
- *The History of Homelessness in the United States, supra* note 65, at 178. ↑
- Katie J. Wells, Policy-Failing: A Repealed Right to Shelter, 41 Urb. Geography 1139, 1143 (2019). ↑
- Rankin, supra note 7, at 101. ↑
- Wells, supra note 69, at 1143. ↑
- Id.; The History of Homelessness in the United States, supra note 65, at 178 (internal citation omitted). ↑
- See Leon Lazaroff, Shelters Go Private: Is It a Help or Hinderance?, Christian Sci. Monitor (July 8, 1998), https://www.csmonitor.com/1998/0708/070898.us.us.3.html [https://perma.cc/7UKM-KF6Y] (explaining that “privately run shelters under the management of groups such as the Salvation Army and Volunteers of America are characteristic of most cities and rural communities”). ↑
- See Maria Foscarinis, Beyond Homelessness: Ethics, Advocacy, and Strategy, 12 St. Louis U. Pub. L. Rev. 37, 44 (1993). ↑
- See Livingston, supra note 58, at 601–06 (detailing the legislative responses to Papachristou and similar court cases). ↑
- See, e.g., Phx., Ariz. City Code §§ 23-7 (aggressive solicitation), 23-8 (loitering), 23-9 (obstructing sidewalks), 23-11 (nuisance), 23-30 (urban camping), 33-2 (pitching tents), 36-131.01 (soliciting employment), 36-401(4) (remaining at a transit station). ↑
- NLCHP, Housing Not Handcuffs, supra note 44, at 37 (“Our research reveals that laws punishing the life-sustaining conduct of homeless people have increased in every measured category since that time, and in some cases dramatically so.”). ↑
- See id. at 38. ↑
- See, e.g., Phx., Ariz. City Code § 23-30(B) (defining camping to include: “sleeping activities, or making preparations to sleep, including the laying down of bedding for the purpose of sleeping, or storing personal belongings, or making any fire, or using any tents or shelter or other structure or vehicle for sleeping or doing any digging or earth breaking or carrying on cooking activities”). ↑
- See, e.g., Glendale, Ariz. Mun. Code art. VIII § 25-90(a) (2018) (“It shall be unlawful for any person to camp upon any public or private land, whether or not such camping takes place in a motor vehicle.”). ↑
- NLCHP, Housing Not Handcuffs, supra note 44, at 38. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. at 50. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. at 53. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. at 15. ↑
- See Rankin, supra note 7, at 123–24 (citing Nat’l Law Ctr. On Homelessness & Poverty, Homelessness in America: Overview of Data and Causes (2015), https://homelesslaw.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/10/Homeless_Stats_Fact_Sheet.pdf [https://perma.cc/T634-SWKU]). ↑
- *Rankin, supra *note 7, at 123. ↑
- Id. at 122. ↑
- Id. ↑
- See Christopher Herring, Cruel Streets: Criminalizing Homelessness in San Francisco 43 (2020) (Ph.D. dissertation, University of California, Berkeley), https://escholarship.org/uc/item/39k7400g [https://perma.cc/3SNX-CXQ2] (explaining that, in San Francisco, an estimated “90% of police and homeless interactions across the city are initiated through complaints”). ↑
- Sarah Holder, Why Calling the Police About Homeless People Isn’t Working, Bloomberg (Sept. 25, 2019), https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2019-09-25/should-you-call-to-report-a-homeless-person [https://perma.cc/53H5-DD7A]. ↑
- See Herring, supra note 93, at 34 (“[S]cholars have characterized quality of life ordinances and their associated policing as cornerstones of the carceral city and urban revanchism aimed at purifying the streets and sidewalks of visible poverty for businesses, tourists, and wealthier residents under the banner of reclaiming the public space for bourgeois consumption.”) (internal citations omitted). ↑
- Id. at 44–45; McJunkin, supra note 9, at 971–72; Maria Foscarinis, Kelly Cunningham-Bowers & Kristen E. Brown, Out of Sight - Out of Mind?: The Continuing Trend Toward the Criminalization of Homelessness, 6 Geo. J. Poverty L. & Pol’y 145, 162 (1999). ↑
- See, e.g., Herring, supra note 93, at 97–98. ↑
- Rankin, supra note 7, at 106–07; see also Sara K. Rankin, Hiding Homelessness: The Transcarceration of Homelessness, 109 Calif. L. Rev. 559, 589 (2021) (“For cities, criminalization is the common default. It empowers the most immediate, albeit temporary, removals of homeless people from public view and creates the short-term illusion that the problem has been mitigated.”). ↑
- See Kevin Morison, Rachel Arietti, Allison Heider, Sarah Mostyn, Dan Alioto, James McGinty, Jason Cheney & Craig Fischer, The Police Response to Homelessness 3 (2018). ↑
- See, e.g., Joel Grover & Josh Davis, Homeless Encampments Spread to Beaches, Golf Courses as City Takes Hands-Off Approach, NBC L.A. (Sept. 4, 2020), https://www.nbclosangeles.com/investigations/omeless-encampments-spread-to-beaches-golf-courses-as-city-takes-hands-off-approach/2423332/ [https://perma.cc/TCC3-4R5X] (“City officials have publicly stated that during the pandemic, no one who is homeless will be moved from their current location, citing CDC guidance, which says moving anyone could help spread COVID.”); Eric Marotta, Akron to Start Clearing Homeless Camps, Citing “Housing First” Policy, Akron Beacon J. (June 20, 2021), https://www.beaconjournal.com/story/news/2021/06/20/adoping-housing-first-policy-akron-begins-clearing-homeless-camps-monday/7731457002/ [https://perma.cc/K8D3-989A] (“During the pandemic, the city chose a hands-off approach to the city’s homeless, as shelter space was scarce due to population restrictions on group settings, and many homeless were fearful of being grouped up in such settings.”). ↑
- See Bryan Gallion, Brenda Wintrode, Julia Lerner, Maya Pottiger, Nick McCool, Lilian Eden, Katy Seiter, Megan Calfas, Joe Dworetzky, Vanessa Ochavillo, Everitt Rosen & Jonmaesha Beltran, As the Wealthy Move in, Homeless People Are Pushed out, Cap. News Serv. Md. (July 13, 2020), https://homeless.cnsmaryland.org/2020/07/13/as-the-wealthy-move-in-homeless-people-are-pushed-out [https://perma.cc/DP9R-9J8T]. ↑
- See id. ↑
- See, e.g., Brittany Scott, Is Urban Policy Making Way for the Wealthy? How a Human Rights Approach Challenges the Purging of Poor Communities from U.S. Cities, 45 Colum. Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 863, 884–89 (2014) (discussing Los Angeles’s Skid Row). Phoenix lawmakers recently proposed a designated homeless encampment area. Jessica Boehm, Bill Would Establish Homeless Camping Areas, Make It Illegal for People to Sleep on the Street in Arizona, AZ Central (Apr. 1, 2021), https://www.azcentral.com/story/news/politics/legislature/2021/04/01/arizona-bill-would-ban-street-camping-create-sanctioned-homeless-camps/4837941001/ [https://perma.cc/G88D-R7SQ]. ↑
- NLCHP, Housing Not Handcuffs, supra note 44, at 50. ↑
- Id. at 51. ↑
- See Sara K. Rankin, Civilly Criminalizing Homelessness, 56 Harv. C.R.-C.L. L. Rev. 367, 406–08 (2021). ↑
- See Morison et al., supra note 99, at 5–7 (explaining that the police tools of arrest and incarceration should be a last resort and encouraging other agencies’ involvement with homeless populations). ↑
- See, e.g., Allison Frankel, Scout Katovich & Hillary Vedvig, Forum: Forced into Breaking the Law, New Haven Reg. (Nov. 17, 2016), https://www.nhregister.com/columnists/article/Forum-Forced-into-breaking-the-law-11319038.php [https://perma.cc/N4SZ-3FEF]. ↑
- See Melissa Hellmann, For Homeless Seattleites, A Reprieve from the Debilitating Burden of Warrants, Seattle Wkly. (Jan. 10, 2018), https://www.seattleweekly.com/news/for-homeless-seattleites-a-reprieve-from-the-debilitating-burden-of-warrants/ [https://perma.cc/7WCK-27TS] (citing transportation, illness, and mental health as additional factors that reduce homeless attendance at court dates). ↑
- See Ethan Corey & Puck Lo, The “Failure to Appear” Fallacy, Appeal (Jan. 9, 2019), https://theappeal.org/the-failure-to-appear-fallacy/ [https://perma.cc/CFH5-NPBY] (explaining that a disproportionate number of failures to appear can be attributed to individuals who are homeless or mentally ill). ↑
- In Phoenix, urban camping is a Class 1 misdemeanor, punishable by up to six months in jail and up to a $2500 fine. Am. C.L. Union of Arizona, Homeless in Phoenix: Know Your Rights 3, https://www.acluaz.org/sites/default/files/field_documents/homeless_rights_in_phoenix.pdf [https://perma.cc/CNR4-R3EQ]. ↑
- See Madeline Bailey, Erica Crew & Madz Reeve, No Access to Justice: Breaking the Cycle of Homelessness and Jail 7, Vera Inst. of Just. (Aug. 2020), https://www.safetyandjusticechallenge.org/wp-content/uploads/2020/08/homelessness-brief-web.pdf [https://perma.cc/89Y8-4MTW] (finding that homeless individuals burdened with legal debt “experienced nearly two additional years of homelessness, after considering the effects of race, age, and gender”). ↑
- See Jessica Guynn, “Hidden Homeless Crisis”: After Losing Jobs and Homes, More People Are Living in Cars and RVs and It’s Getting Worse, USA Today (Feb. 15, 2021), https://www.usatoday.com/story/money/2021/02/12/covid-unemployment-layoffs-foreclosure-eviction-homeless-car-rv/6713901002/ [https://perma.cc/VY9W-68E3]; Edwin Caro, Homelessness and Health Justice, 30 Annals Health L. Advance Directive 143, 144 (2020). ↑
- Hellmann, supra note 109. ↑
- McJunkin, supra note 9, at 963–68 (describing the punitive and costly nature of custodial arrest). ↑
- Id. at 965–66. ↑
- Id. at 965. ↑
- Id. ↑
- See Rankin, supra note 7, at 109 (“Several studies show it is far more expensive to criminalize poverty and homelessness than it is to pursue non-punitive alternatives such as permanent supportive housing, and mental health and substantive abuse treatment.”). ↑
- Audrey Jensen, Jill Ryan, Chloe Jones & Madeline Ackley, Two Cities Tried to Fix Homelessness, Only One Succeeded, Cronkite News (Dec. 14, 2020), https://cronkitenews.azpbs.org/howardcenter/caring-for-covid-homeless/stories/homeless-funding-housing-first.html [https://perma.cc/GWJ4-NA4N] (documenting reductions in homeless populations in Houston and San Diego); Supportive Housing Reduces Homelessness—And Lowers Health Care Costs by Millions, Rand Corp. (June 27, 2018), https://www.rand.org/blog/rand-review/2018/06/supportive-housing-reduces-homelessness-and-lowers.html [https://perma.cc/V2FV-XZFE]. But see Stephen Eide, Housing First and Homelessness: The Rhetoric and the Reality, Manhattan Inst. (Apr. 21, 2020), https://www.manhattan-institute.org/housing-first-effectiveness [https://perma.cc/944W-DQYR] (explaining that housing-first models are more effective on the individual, rather than community, level). ↑
- In September 2019, the Council of Economic Advisors released a white paper advocating increased policing and “quality of life” ordinances to reduce unsheltered homelessness by making living on the streets less “tolerab[le].” See Council of Econ. Advisors, The State of Homelessness in America 18–19 (2019), https://www.nhipdata.org/local/upload/file/The-State-of-Homelessness-in-America.pdf [https://perma.cc/2YCE-ED7A]. ↑
- Baskett, supra note 25, at 601 (describing cities’ widespread adoption of the “velvet hammer” approach to homelessness, which involves “stripping away social services and criminalizing [behaviors] that ‘enable’ homelessness”). ↑
- Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville, 405 U.S. 156, 158 (1972). The city’s ordinance outlawed the following: Rogues and vagabonds, or dissolute persons who go about begging, common gamblers, persons who use juggling or unlawful games or plays, common drunkards, common night walkers, thieves, pilferers or pickpockets, traders in stolen property, lewd, wanton and lascivious persons, keepers of gambling places, common railers and brawlers, persons wandering or strolling around from place to place without any lawful purpose or object, habitual loafers, disorderly persons, persons neglecting all lawful business and habitually spending their time by frequenting houses of ill fame, gaming houses, or places where alcoholic beverages are sold or served, persons able to work but habitually living upon the earnings of their wives or minor children. Id. at 158 n.1. ↑
- Id. at 166–69. ↑
- See Liz Daube, The Rules of Being Homeless, Jacksonville Daily Rec. (Aug. 10, 2006), https://www.jaxdailyrecord.com/article/rules-being-homeless [https://perma.cc/P868-Z468]. ↑
- Ingraham v. Wright, 430 U.S. 651, 667 (1977). ↑
- See generally Robinson v. California, 370 U.S. 660 (1962) (holding unconstitutional a state statute that punished the “status” of drug addiction). ↑
- Id. at 667. The law at issue was a California statute that made it a criminal offense to “be addicted to the use of narcotics.” Id. at 660 (internal citation omitted). ↑
- See, e.g., Headley v. Selkowitz, 171 So. 2d 368, 370 (Fla. 1965); Alegata v. Commonwealth, 231 N.E.2d 201, 207 (Mass. 1967); Wheeler v. Goodman, 306 F. Supp. 58, 64 (W.D.N.C. 1969), vacated on other grounds, 401 U.S. 987 (1971). ↑
- Powell v. Texas, 392 U.S. 514, 533 (1968). ↑
- See, e.g., Tobe v. City of Santa Ana, 892 P.2d 1145, 1166–67 (Cal. 1995); Joel v. City of Orlando, 232 F.3d 1353, 1362 (11th Cir. 2000). ↑
- See, e.g., Joyce v. City of San Francisco, 846 F. Supp. 843, 857 (N.D. Cal. 1994). ↑
- Jones v. City of Los Angeles, 444 F.3d 1118, 1137 (9th Cir. 2006). ↑
- See Jones v. City of Los Angeles, 505 F.3d 1006 (9th Cir. 2007). ↑
- Martin v. City of Boise, 902 F.3d 1031 (9th Cir. 2018); see, e.g., Baskett, supra note 25, at 596 (noting that “Martin v. City of Boise has been celebrated as a victory against these ordinances”); Rankin, supra note 98, at 562 (noting that “homeless rights advocates celebrated” the Martin decision); Press Release, Settlement Reached in Groundbreaking Martin v. City of Boise Case, Nat’l Homelessness L. Ctr. (Feb. 8, 2021), https://homelesslaw.org/settlement-martin-v-boise-case [https://perma.cc/ZFT6-KGVQ] (noting that “[a]dvocates have hailed” the Martin decision). ↑
- As the Supreme Court has explained, substantive due process “forbids the government to infringe certain ‘fundamental’ liberty interests at all, no matter what process is provided, unless the infringement is narrowly tailored to serve a compelling state interest.” Reno v. Flores, 507 U.S. 292, 302 (1993) (emphasis in original) (citations omitted). ↑
- Heather K. Gerken, Larry and Lawrence, 42 Tulsa L. Rev. 843, 849 (2007). ↑
- See Joel v. City of Orlando, 232 F.3d 1353, 1359–62 (11th Cir. 2000); Roulette v. City of Seattle, 97 F.3d 300, 315–16 (9th Cir. 1996). ↑
- See, e.g., Pottinger v. City of Miami, 810 F. Supp. 1551, 1580 (S.D. Fla. 1992); Johnson v. Bd. of Police Comm’rs, 351 F. Supp. 2d 929, 949 (E.D. Mo. 1994); see generally Andrew J. Liese, We Can Do Better: Anti-Homeless Ordinances as Violations of State Substantive Due Process Law, 59 Vand. L. Rev. 1413 (2006) (arguing that anti-homeless ordinances are most effectively challenged under due process clauses of state constitutions). ↑
- Roulette, 97 F.3d at 300. ↑
- Id. at 306. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Joel v. City of Orlando, 232 F.3d 1353, 1359–62 (11th Cir. 2000). The defendant also unsuccessfully challenged the ordinance under the Constitution’s Equal Protection Clause and Eighth Amendment. ↑
- Id. at 1359. ↑
- Id. at 1359 n.3. ↑
- See, e.g., Pottinger v. City of Miami, 810 F. Supp. 1551, 1580 (S.D. Fla. 1992); Johnson v. Bd. of Police Comm’rs, 351 F. Supp. 2d 929, 949 (E.D. Mo. 2004). The Supreme Court has recognized on numerous occasions that the right to interstate travel is “fundamental,” and is therefore subject to strict scrutiny when infringed upon by the government. See, e.g., Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.S. 330 (1972); Oregon v. Mitchell, 400 U.S. 112 (1970); Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.S. 618 (1969); United States v. Guest, 383 U.S. 745 (1966). ↑
- See, e.g., Streetwatch v. Nat’l R.R. Passenger Corp., 875 F. Supp. 1055, 1064 (S.D.N.Y. 1995). ↑
- See, e.g., Anderson v. City of Portland, No. 08-1447-AA, 2009 WL 2386056, at 10 (D. Or. July 31, 2009) (explaining that plaintiffs “allege that police officers have told them to ‘move along’ when sleeping in public and conducted camp clean-ups and seized their property,” but that such allegations do not demonstrate “that the City has attempted to restrain their movement”); Davison v. City of Tucson, 924 F. Supp. 989, 993 (D. Ariz. 1996) (“The Defendants’ action does not impede the travel of any of the named plaintiffs because they do not seek to travel* anywhere; they seek only to remain.”) (emphasis in original). ↑
- See Lindsey v. Normet, 405 U.S. 56, 73 (1972) (arguing for the “need for decent shelter” and the “right to retain peaceful possession of one’s home”). ↑
- Dennis D. Hirsch, Making Shelter Work: Placing Conditions on an Employable Person’s Right to Shelter, 100 Yale L.J. 491, 491 (1990) (“One of the major responses by members of the legal community has been to argue for a right to shelter that would obligate the government (generally state or local) to provide housing to all homeless persons who request it.”). ↑
- See, e.g., id.; Kevin P. Sherburne, Comment, The Judiciary and the Ad Hoc Development of A Legal Right to Shelter, 12 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 193, 202–15 (1989). ↑
- Ben Holtzman, When the Homeless Took over, Shelterforce (Oct. 11, 2019), https://shelterforce.org/2019/10/11/when-the-homeless-took-over/ [https://perma.cc/5RAL-RNN6]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- See infra Part II.A. ↑
- See infra Part II.B. ↑
- See infra Part II.A–B. ↑
- See infra Part II.A–B. ↑
- See Lindsey v. Normet, 405 U.S. 56, 58 (1972). ↑
- Id. at 74. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- See, e.g., Hilton v. City of New Haven, 661 A.2d 973, 984 (Conn. 1995) (rejecting plaintiffs’ claim to an affirmative right to shelter under three unique provisions of the Connecticut Constitution); see also Sherburne, supra note 152, at 220 (citing Ala. Const. art. IV. § 88 (authorizing legislature to require counties to provide for poor individuals); Kan. Const. art. 7, § 4 (requiring counties to provide aid to misfortunate individuals); Mont. Const. art. XII, § 3(3) (requiring legislature to provide economic assistance to needy individuals); Okla. Const. art. 17, § 3 (requiring counties to provide for persons in need); Ga. Const. art. IX, § V (empowering counties to provide support for poor individuals); Haw. Const. art. IX, § 3 (empowering the state to provide aid to needy individuals)). ↑
- See Callahan v. Carey, No. 79-42582 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Aug. 26, 1981) (final judgment by consent decree). ↑
- N.Y. Const. art. XVII, § 1. ↑
- Kim Hopper, The Ordeal of Shelter: Continuities and Discontinuities in the Public Response to Homelessness, 4 Notre Dame J.L. Ethics & Pub. Pol’y 301, 318 (1990) (citing Callahan v. Carey, 188 N.Y.L.J., Dec. 11, 1979, at 10, col. 4 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Dec. 5, 1979)). ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Wells, supra note 69, at 1143. ↑
- Housing and Support Services, Off. Temp. & Disability Assistance, https://otda.ny.gov/programs/housing/#header [https://perma.cc/ZPE4-UHAV]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Frequently Asked Questions, N.Y.C. Dep’t Homeless Servs., https://www1.nyc.gov/site/dhs/about/frequently-asked-questions.page [https://perma.cc/RR2S-9N4Y]. ↑
- Inside DHS, N.Y.C. Dep’t of Homeless Servs., https://web.archive.org/web/20220124150115/https://www1.nyc.gov/site/dhs/about/inside-dhs.page. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Frequently Asked Questions, supra note 174. ↑
- N.Y. Crim. Proc. Law § 2.20(1) (McKinney 2005). These powers include inter alia: (a) The power to make warrantless arrests pursuant to section 140.25 of this chapter. (b) The power to use physical force and deadly physical force in making an arrest or preventing an escape pursuant to section 35.30 of the penal law. (c) The power to carry out warrantless searches whenever such searches are constitutionally permissible and acting pursuant to their special duties. Id. ↑
- W. Va. Code § 9-6-4. ↑
- W. Va. Code § 9-6-1(6). ↑
- W. Va. Code § 9-6-1(5). ↑
- 303 S.E.2d 245, 251 (W.Va. 1983). ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. (internal quotation omitted). ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- W. Va. Dep’t of Health & Hum. Res., Funding Announcement for Homeless Services 3–4 (2019), https://dhhr.wv.gov/bcf/Providers/Documents/Homeless%20Services%20Announcement.pdf [https://perma.cc/A7CT-C762]. ↑
- W. Va. Dep’t of Health & Hum. Res., Homeless Services Policy 10 (2016), https://dhhr.wv.gov/bcf/policy/Documents/Homeless Policy.pdf [https://perma.cc/K73F-WFR2]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. at 3. ↑
- Id. at 8. ↑
- Id. ↑
- West Virginia PATH Program Addresses Rural Homelessness, Substance Abuse & Mental Health Servs. Admin. (Apr. 30, 2020), https://www.samhsa.gov/homelessness-programs-resources/hpr-resources/path-program-rural-homelessness [https://perma.cc/UB29-Z5N2]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- See W. Va. Dep’t of Health & Hum. Res., supra note 187, at 7–9. ↑
- The Department of Housing and Urban Development also has a “Resource Locator” feature, although it is significantly less user-friendly. See Homeless Information: West Virginia, U.S. Dep’t of Hous. & Urb. Dev., https://www.hud.gov/states/west_virginia/homeless [https://perma.cc/TG57-K5LT]. ↑
- See West Virginia Homeless Shelters, Homeless Shelters Directory, https://www.homelessshelterdirectory.org/westvirginia.html [https://perma.cc/AWU2-PVLR] ↑
- Id. ↑
- See, e.g., Homeless Information: West Virginia, supra note 196. ↑
- Wells, supra note 69, at 1143–45. ↑
- Id. at 1144 (internal citations omitted). ↑
- Id. at 1145. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. As researcher Katie Wells has reported: “The apex of CCNV’s activism in 1984 was a vow to fast until the federal government agreed to renovate a federal building in Washington, D.C. in which CCNV sheltered 850 people each night. After CCNV’s most prominent member, Mitch Snyder, fasted for 51 days, federal officials agreed to the demand. That night a 60 Minutes television segment covered the story. The timing of the fast no doubt helped to ensure the passage of the right to shelter initiative three days later.” Id. at 1147. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. at 1148. ↑
- Id. at 1149–50. ↑
- D.C. Code § 4-755.01(a) (2005). ↑
- D.C. Law 21-141 (2016). ↑
- Id. at § 2(3). ↑
- Ward 1’s shelter just finished construction in early 2021 and was projected to start serving families around March 2021, at the earliest. See Jenny Gathright, D.C. Completes Ward 1 Family Homeless Shelter, Capping Years-Long Effort, NPR (Feb. 4, 2021), https://www.npr.org/local/305/2021/02/04/964014402/d-c-completes-ward-1-family-homeless-shelter-capping-years-long-effort [https://perma.cc/MT3H-2J4W]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- See, e.g., How to Access Shelter, Dep’t of Hum. Servs., https://dhs.dc.gov/page/how-access-shelter [https://perma.cc/5JG7-FX7Z]. ↑
- Services for Individuals Experiencing Homelessness, Dep’t of Hum. Servs., https://dhs.dc.gov/page/services-individuals-experiencing-homelessness [https://perma.cc/Q5VC-77XB]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Mass. Gen. Laws ch. 450 (1983) (amended 2014). But cf. Laticia Walker-Simpson, Life Raft or Quicksand?: Emergency Assistance’s Role in Greater Boston’s Homeless Crisis, 64 Bos. Bar J. 23, 23 (2020) (mentioning that Massachusetts’ eligibility requirements are much more restrictive than they first appear). ↑
- Basic Facts on Homelessness and Housing in Massachusetts, Mass. Coal. for the Homeless, https://mahomeless.org/basic-facts/ [https://perma.cc/Z767-738Q]. ↑
- Lucy Ellis, Massachusetts Family Homelessness System, Bos. Found. (Feb. 22, 2017), https://www.tbf.org/old-blog/2017/february/massachusetts-family-homelessness-system [https://perma.cc/PZ9W-6K4L]. ↑
- Ruth Bourquin, Basic Shelter Rights (Emergency Assistance), MassLegalHelp (Jan. 2011), https://www.masslegalhelp.org/income-benefits/basic-shelter-rights [http://perma.cc/6EGU-4RP9]. The income level eligibility determination for Emergency Assistance is based on a comparison of family size with monthly and yearly total salary. Emergency Assistance Income Limits, MassLegalHelp (Jan. 2022), https://www.masslegalhelp.org/income-benefits/emergency-assistance-income-limits [https://perma.cc/3SRX-5HAW]. ↑
- Bourquin, supra note 220. ↑
- Id. ↑
- See, e.g., Sascha Brodsky, Choosing Between Shelter and School, Atlantic (Dec. 8, 2016), https://www.theatlantic.com/education/archive/2016/12/shelter-versus-school/509825/ [https://perma.cc/H792-4P8P]. ↑
- See, e.g., Alexa Gagosz, She Took Her Daughter and Ran from an Abusive Relationship. Now They’re Homeless, Bos. Globe (Oct. 21, 2021), https://www.bostonglobe.com/2021/10/21/metro/she-took-her-daughter-ran-an-abusive-relationship-now-theyre-homeless/ [https://perma.cc/YCC6-ZP7K]. ↑
- Bourquin, supra note 220. ↑
- Overview of the Department of Housing and Community Development, Mass.gov, https://www.mass.gov/info-details/overview-of-the-department-of-housing-and-community-development [https://perma.cc/PTK8-MM8D]. Their website defines the types of housing as follows. Scattered site: Pregnant women and families live in an apartment where they have their own bedroom/s, bathroom, kitchen, and living room. This accommodation can be in a multifamily home or in an apartment building. These buildings may also house families that are not in the EA program. Co-shelter site: Pregnant women and families share an apartment with another woman or family in the EA program. They have their own bedroom/s but share common areas that include a living room, kitchen, and bathroom. These apartments are located in multifamily buildings, which may contain other units that are not part of the EA program. Congregate site: Each pregnant woman or family lives in their own room at the shelter and shares communal spaces such as living rooms, dining rooms, and kitchens with the other resident families. Some of these facilities may also include residential and day programs other than the EA program. Hotel: Pregnant women and families live in hotel rooms with a refrigerator, microwave, and toaster oven; bathroom; and sleeping area. The Commonwealth has reduced the reliance on hotels and now shelters all pregnant women and families in the EA program in the same hotel. Id. ↑
- Mass. Coal. for the Homeless, supra note 218. ↑
- Governor’s Council of Regional Homeless Advisors Convenes in LA, Cnty. of L.A., https://ridley-thomas.lacounty.gov/index.php/governors-regional-homeless-advisory-council-convenes-in-la/ [https://perma.cc/5K9X-QG6L]; Matt Levin & Jackie Botts, Cities Should Act on Homelessness or Face Lawsuits, Newsom Task Force Says, Cal Matters (Jan. 14, 2020), https://calmatters.org/housing/2020/01/gavin-newsom-homelessness-task-force/ [https://perma.cc/8GPZ-VYAK]. ↑
- Darrell Steinberg, Op-Ed: Building More Permanent Housing Alone Won’t Solve Homelessness in California, L.A. Times (July 17, 2019), https://www.latimes.com/opinion/story/2019-07-16/op-ed-building-more-permanent-housing-alone-wont-solve-homelessness-in-california [https://perma.cc/UR2G-SRCW]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Anita Chabria, Benjamin Oreskes, & Taryn Lunca, Voters Could Decide if California Cities Will Be Punished for Not Reducing Homelessness, L.A. Times (Jan. 13, 2020), https://www.latimes.com/california/story/2020-01-13/homeless-housing-task-force-california-constitutional-amendment [https://perma.cc/SEA2-ARPU]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Andrea Noble, California Plan to Reduce Homelessness Forces Cities, Counties to Step up, Route Fifty (Jan. 24, 2020), https://www.route-fifty.com/health-human-services/2020/01/california-plan-reduce-homelessness-forces-cities-counties-step/162653/ [https://perma.cc/5DRJ-8QKG]. ↑
- Chabria et al., supra note 231. ↑
- A.B. 3269, State Leg., Reg. Sess. (Cal. 2020). ↑
- Patrick McGreevy, No Deal Yet in Sacramento to Help Struggling California Renters, L.A. Times (Aug. 20, 2020), https://www.latimes.com/california/story/2020-08-20/no-deal-yet-on-help-california-renters-evictions-housing [https://perma.cc/KB8X-UVRM]. ↑
- See Bill Status, AB-3269 State and Local Agencies: Homelessness Plan, Cal. Legis. Info., https://leginfo.legislature.ca.gov/faces/billStatusClient.xhtml?bill_id=201920200AB3269 [https://perma.cc/4VL7-GCSG]. ↑
- See, e.g., Pottinger v. City of Miami, 810 F. Supp. 1551, 1565 (S.D. Fla. 1992) (“As long as the homeless plaintiffs do not have a single place where they can lawfully be, the challenged ordinances, as applied to them, effectively punish them for something for which they may not be convicted under the eighth amendment—sleeping, eating and other innocent conduct.”); Johnson v. City of Dallas, 860 F. Supp. 344, 351 (N.D. Tex. 1994) (“[A]s long as the homeless have no other place to be, they may not be prevented from sleeping in public.”); Jones v. City of Los Angeles, 444 F.3d 1118, 1137 (9th Cir. 2006) (“Undisputed evidence in the record establishes that at the time they were cited or arrested, Appellants had no choice other than to be on the streets.”). ↑
- Pottinger, 810 F. Supp. at 1557–60. ↑
- Id. at 1554. ↑
- Id. at 1564. ↑
- Id. at 1565. The Eighth Amendment claim was one of many constitutional victories for the plaintiff class. The Court also ruled that Miami’s practices violated the Due Process and Equal Protection clauses, as well as the Fourth Amendment’s prohibition on unreasonable searches and seizures. Id. at 1583. ↑
- The case eventually settled after multiple appeals and nearly ten years of litigation. See Pottinger v. City of Miami, 359 F. Supp. 3d 1177, 1179 (S.D. Fla. 2019). Since the terms of settlement are binding only on the municipality that is a party to the litigation, the District Court’s constitutional rulings have no precedential value, even in that District. McJunkin, supra note 9, at 977. As I have noted elsewhere, the frequency of settlement, combined with the protracted nature of these class-action suits, makes constitutional litigation an ineffective tool for broad decriminalization efforts by homeless advocates. Id. at 977–79. ↑
- See, e.g., Jones v. City of Los Angeles, 444 F.3d 1118, 1136–38 (9th Cir. 2006). ↑
- See id. at 1132 (“Because there is substantial and undisputed evidence that the number of homeless persons in Los Angeles far exceeds the number of available shelter beds at all times, including on the nights of their arrest or citation, Los Angeles has encroached upon Appellants’ Eighth Amendment protections by criminalizing the unavoidable act of sitting, lying, or sleeping at night while being involuntarily homeless.”). ↑
- Id. at 1137, 1123. ↑
- Id. at 1120. ↑
- Id. at 1136. ↑
- Id. at 1132. ↑
- Id. at 1122. ↑
- Martin v. City of Boise, 902 F.3d 1031 (9th Cir. 2018), amended by 920 F.3d 584 (9th Cir. 2019) (en banc). ↑
- Martin, 902 F.3d at 1035. ↑
- Id. at 1036–37, 1041. ↑
- Id. at 1048. ↑
- See, e.g., Press Release, Appeals Court Ruling Ends the Criminalization of Homelessness, Am. C.L. Union (Apr. 14, 2006), https://www.aclu.org/press-releases/aclu-southern-california-wins-historic-victory-homeless-rights-case [https://perma.cc/JMU9-7TK6]; Settlement Reached in Groundbreaking Martin v. City of Boise Case, supra note 135. ↑
- See Erasmus Baxter, Phoenix’s Draft Homelessness Plan Raises Hopes and Concerns, Phx. New Times (July 7, 2020), https://www.phoenixnewtimes.com/news/phoenix-draft-homeless-plan-hopes-portal-advocates-community-gallego-11478370 [https://perma.cc/D276-MLZ6]. ↑
- See Madeline Ackley, Phoenix Still Criminalizes Homelessness, Despite Court Ruling, Protestors Say, AZ Mirror (Jan. 9, 2020), https://www.azmirror.com/2020/01/09/phoenix-still-criminalizes-homelessness-despite-court-ruling-protesters-say [https://perma.cc/8EV6-F26C] (reporting that Glendale and Tempe have stopped enforcing urban camping laws). ↑
- Rankin, supra note 98, at 566. ↑
- See id. at 580. “Sociologists sometimes refer to this dynamic of interchangeability between mental hospitals and incarceration as transcarceration because vulnerable people are transferred between carceral confinement and other forms of forced institutionalization.” Id. at 583. ↑
- Id. at 565, 590–94. ↑
- Id. at 592–94. ↑
- Id. at 594–98. ↑
- Id. at 595. ↑
- Id. at 598–99. ↑
- Id. at 600–02. ↑
- See Baskett, supra note 25, at 605. “Because the cornerstone of Director Marbut’s ‘velvet hammer’ approach is the construction of large, centralized facilities that are available to the homeless twenty-four hours a day, there may be very few instances in which no alternative sleeping space is available and, therefore, little protection for the homeless population against the criminalization of persons sleeping outside on public property.” Id. at 604. ↑
- R. George Wright, Homelessness, Criminal Responsibility, and the Pathologies of Policy: Triangulating on a Constitutional Right to Housing, 93 St. John’s L. Rev. 427, 436–37 (2019). ↑
- Eighth Amendment – Criminalization of Homelessness – Ninth Circuit Refuses to Reconsider Invalidation of Ordinances Completely Banning Sleeping and Camping in Public. – Martin v. City of Boise, 920 F.3d 584 (9th Cir. 2019), 133 Harv. L. Rev. 699, 704 (2019). ↑
- See Rankin, supra note 98, at 612–13. ↑
- See Jamelia N. Morgan, Policing Marginality in Public Space, 81 Ohio St. L.J. 1045, 1045 (2020). ↑
- Id. at 1047. ↑
- Id. at 1053–54. ↑
- See id. ↑
- Id. at 1059–60. For instance, the Court fails to address how the quality of homeless shelter or the location of a homeless shelter may factor into whether a shelter is considered “practically available.” Id. ↑
- Id. at 1060. ↑
- Id. at 1062–63. ↑
- See, e.g., Joel v. City of Orlando, 232 F.3d 1353, 1361–62 (11th Cir. 2000) (finding that the ordinance challenged did not criminalize involuntary behavior as shelter beds were available). ↑
- See Martin v. City of Boise, 902 F.3d 1031, 1048 n.8 (9th Cir. 2018) (“Naturally, our holding does not cover individuals who do have access to adequate temporary shelter, whether because they have the means to pay for it or because it is realistically available to them for free, but who choose not to use it.”) (emphasis in original). ↑
- See, e.g., Phx., Ariz. City Code § 23-30 (criminalizing urban camping without regard to shelter availability). ↑
- See Morgan, supra note 270, at 1053 (“[L]ocal jurisdictions and communities have used a number of criminal laws . . . to police access to use and enjoyment of public space.”); Rankin, supra note 98, at 589 (noting that “narratives generally frame the visibility of homeless people as the problem . . . [s]o rather than prioritize solutions to homelessness, cities continue to excise homeless people”). ↑
- Rankin, supra note 98, at 589 (“[Criminalization] empowers the most immediate, albeit temporary, removals of homeless people from public view and creates the short-term illusion that the problem has been mitigated.”). ↑
- See Martin, 902 F.3d at 1048 & n.8. ↑
- See Adler, supra note 52, at 215–16. ↑
- See supra text accompanying notes 54–55. ↑
- Lindsey Davis, Coal. for the Homeless, View from the Street: Unsheltered New Yorkers and the Need for Safety, Dignity, and Agency 11 (2021) (“Seventy-seven percent of respondents stated that they have tried the municipal shelter system and instead choose to stay on the streets.”); see also Jeremy Jojola & Katie Wilcox, We Asked 100 Homeless People if They’d Rather Sleep Outside or in a Shelter, 9 News (Nov. 21, 2017), https://www.9news.com/article/news/investigations/we-asked-100-homeless-people-if-theyd-rather-sleep-outside-or-in-a-shelter/73-493418852 [https://perma.cc/FK2A-L3V5] (conducting informal survey of one hundred homeless individuals in Denver and finding that 70 percent prefer sleeping on the streets to shelter services). ↑
- See infra Part III.A–D. ↑
- Joy H. Kim, The Case Against Criminalizing Homelessness: Functional Barriers to Shelters and Homeless Individuals’ Lack of Choice, 95 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1150, 1176–84 (2020) (exploring the lack of choice for individuals experiencing homelessness—even when shelter is “available”). ↑
- Joshua T. Ellsworth, Street Crime Victimization Among Homeless Adults: A Review of the Literature, 14 Victims & Offenders 96, 112 (2019) (“When pooled, extant data on homeless street crime victimization indicates that assault occurs roughly 11 times more frequently; incidence of robbery may be more than 12 times more prevalent, while theft may occur more than 20 times as frequently as in the general population.”). ↑
- Inst. of Med. Comm. on Health Care for Homeless People, Health Problems of Homeless People, in Homelessness, Health, and Human Needs 39, 41 (1988) (“Homelessness increases the risk of developing health problems such as diseases of the extremities and skin disorders; it increases the possibility of trauma, especially as a result of physical assault or rape.”). ↑
- See Jason Albertson, Daisy Anarchy, Rachel Brahinsky, Jennifer Friedenbach, Chanel Kennedy, Jonathon Hootman, Bob Offer-Westort, Tomas Picarello & Brent Sipes, Shelter Shock: Abuse, Cruelty, and Neglect in San Francisco’s Shelter System 7 (May 2007), https://www.cohsf.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/08/ShelterShock.pdf [https://perma.cc/LA98-YC4L] (“More than half of respondents, or 55%, reported experiencing abuse inside the shelter,” 14% percent reported experiencing physical violence, 4% reported experiencing sexual abuse, and “one-third (32%) of respondents reported they did not feel safe [inside a shelter].”). ↑
- See Leonard C. Feldman, Citizens Without Shelter: Homelessness, Democracy, and Political Exclusion 96 (Cornell Univ. Press 2004). Degrading conditions, extensive rules, lack of privacy, and surveillance by emergency shelter staff demonstrate certain values and conceptions. Minimal provisions (a cot and a blanket) and minimal privacy (rows of cots in large undivided warehouse spaces) express a vision of the homeless as bare life, as beings stripped of human personhood and individual identity[.] ↑
- See id. ↑
- See id. ↑
- See id. ↑
- Albertson et al., supra note 290, at 7 (“More than half of respondents, or 55%, reported experiencing abuse inside the shelter.”). ↑
- See Janny S. Li & Lianne A. Urada, Cycle of Perpetual Vulnerability for Women Facing Homelessness near an Urban Library in a Major U.S. Metropolitan Area, 17 Int’l J. Env’t Rsch. & Pub. Health (Special Issue) 7 (Aug. 18, 2020), https://www.mdpi.com/1660-4601/17/16/5985/htm [https://perma.cc/KCD5-K72S] (“Women’s only accommodations were said to be important because of the safety issues that women may feel among men, particularly for women escaping intimate partner violence or traveling with children.”). ↑
- Amaka Uchegbu, Homeless Women Find Sexual Violence Part of Life on the Street, Pittsburgh Post-Gazette (Aug. 17, 2015), https://www.post-gazette.com/news/health/2015/08/18/Homeless-women-find-sexual-violence-part-of-life-on-the-street/stories/201507130149 [https://perma.cc/S99N-YQQD]. ↑
- See Kathleen Guarino & Ellen Bassuk, Working with Families Experiencing Homelessness: Understanding Trauma and Its Impact, Signal, Jan.–Mar. 2010, at 14, 16, https://perspectives.waimh.org/wp-content/uploads/sites/9/2017/05/5-Working-with-Families-Experiencing-Homelessness.-Understanding-Trauma-and-its-Impact.pdf [https://perma.cc/CKN5-36LJ] (“As a result of these challenges, women who are homeless and have experienced chronic trauma have considerable difficulties trusting others and accessing help and support for themselves and their children.”). ↑
- Instead of going to shelters, women are more likely than men to turn to families, friends, or acquaintances as a means of finding shelter. See Paula Mayock, Sarah Sheridan, & Sarah Parker, ‘It’s Just Like We’re Going Around in Circles and Going Back to the Same Thing’: The Dynamics of Women’s Unresolved Homelessness, 30 Hous. Stud. 877, 880 (2015); see also id. at 894 (noting that because of intimate partner violence, women attempted to resolve homelessness “independently, primarily because they had lost faith in the ability of ‘the system’ to find a resolution to their situations”). ↑
- Coronavirus Disease (COVID-19): How Is It Transmitted?, World Health Org. (Dec. 23, 2021), https://www.who.int/news-room/q-a-detail/coronavirus-disease-covid-19-how-is-it-transmitted [https://perma.cc/J4QQ-UL7K]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- See Marissa J. Lang, Justin Wm. Moyer & Nitasha Tiku, Cities Struggle to Protect Vulnerable Homeless Populations as Coronavirus Spreads, Wash. Post (Mar. 20, 2020), https://www.washingtonpost.com/local/cities-struggle-to-protect-vulnerable-homeless-populations-as-coronavirus-spreads/2020/03/20/1144249c-67be-11ea-b5f1-a5a804158597_story.html [https://perma.cc/K6Q2-GMUA]. In some shelters, people share rooms and sleep in bunk beds. In others, mats line the floor of empty rooms to squeeze in as many people as possible during the winter months . . . Many shelters do not have room to isolate someone for an extended period. Some already are running low on cleaning supplies, hand sanitizer, food and volunteers to relieve overworked staff. Others have told volunteers to stay home—an effort to limit the number of people in and out of shelters at a time when experts say even asymptomatic people can spread the coronavirus. Id. ↑
- Daniella Silva, With Winter Approaching, Homeless Shelters Face Big Challenges Against Coronavirus, NBC News (Dec. 5, 2020), https://www.nbcnews.com/news/us-news/winter-approaching-homeless-shelters-face-big-challenges-against-coronavirus-n1249906 [https://perma.cc/SV92-E8Y5] (“Homeless shelters have had to adapt this year, with most reducing the number of people allowed inside to limit virus exposure for guests and staff members.”). ↑
- Sarah Holder & Kriston Capps, No Easy Fixes as COVID-19 Hits Homeless Shelters, Bloomberg (Apr. 17, 2020), https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2020-04-17/no-easy-fixes-as-covid-19-hits-homeless-shelters [https://perma.cc/7BWN-PWX7] (observing that “some shelters aren’t necessarily eagerly welcoming state or local government interventions to reduce crowding”). ↑
- Matt Leseman, As the Mask Order Rolls out, Homeless Shelters Ask for Flexibility, KTUU (June 29, 2020), https://www.alaskasnewssource.com/content/news/As-the-mask-order-rolls-out-homeless-shelters-ask-for-flexibility-571557301.html [https://perma.cc/3QZH-GQR3] (“Asking someone to leave for not wearing a mask runs counter to the goal of providing them with a temporary home.”). ↑
- See Lloyd A.C. Chapman, Margot Kushel, Sarah N. Cox, Ashley Scarborough, Caroline Cawley, Trang Q. Nguyen, Isabel Rodriguez-Barraquer, Bryan Greenhouse, Elizabeth Impert & Nathan C. Lo, Comparison of Infection Control Strategies to Reduce COVID-19 Outbreaks in Homeless Shelters in the United States: A Simulation Study, 19 BMC Med. 2 (2021), https://bmcmedicine.biomedcentral.com/articles/10.1186/s12916-021-01965-y#MOESM1 [https://perma.cc/JL3G-JZHK] (reporting data from several cities, including San Francisco, Boston, Seattle, Atlanta, and Los Angeles). ↑
- Ed Susman, Homeless Camps Less Risky Than Shelters for COVID-19, MedPage Today (Oct. 27, 2020), https://www.medpagetoday.com/meetingcoverage/idweek/89353 [https://perma.cc/CX8H-B8CR] (reporting results from Denver). ↑
- See Michelle Moffa, Ryan Cronk, Donald Fejfar, Sarah Dancausse, Leslie Acosta Padilla & Jamie Bartram, A Systematic Scoping Review of Environmental Health Conditions and Hygiene Behaviors in Homeless Shelters, 222 Int’l J. Hygiene & Env’t Health 335, 342 (2019) (finding that, although less than 20 percent of the shelters they surveyed qualified as “overcrowded,” over half of the shelters surveyed reported shelter clients had tuberculosis likely due to crowding and poor ventilation). ↑
- Sékéné Badiaga, Didier Raoult & Philippe Brouqui, Preventing and Controlling Emerging and Reemerging Transmissible Diseases in the Homeless, 14 Emerging Infectious Diseases 1353, 1354 (2008), https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2603102/ [https://perma.cc/MC7U-G3P5] (“The primary health concerns for this population are the overcrowded living conditions that expose them to airborne infections, especially TB, and the lack of personal hygiene and clothing changes that expose them to scabies, infestation with body lice, and louse-borne diseases.”) (internal citation omitted). ↑
- Kim, supra note 287, at 1178. ↑
- Nikita Stewart, As Shelter Population Surges, Housing for Disabled Comes up Short, N.Y. Times (Sept. 16, 2016), https://www.nytimes.com/2016/09/17/nyregion/as-residents-surge-in-new-york-shelters-housing-for-disabled-comes-up-short.html [https://perma.cc/26BB-ZY2X]. ↑
- See id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- U.S. Dep’t of Hous. & Urb. Dev, HUD 2020 Continuum of Care Homeless Assistance Programs Homeless Populations and Subpopulations 2 (Dec. 15, 2020), https://files.hudexchange.info/reports/published/CoC_PopSub_NatlTerrDC_2020.pdf [https://perma.cc/G74H-84DD] (finding that, out of a sample of 580,455 homeless persons, 120,642 were severely mentally ill and 98,646 had a chronic substance abuse disorder). ↑
- Kim, supra note 287, at 1179–82. ↑
- See, e.g., id. at 1180 & n.188 (internal citation omitted). ↑
- See NLCHP, Housing Not Handcuffs, supra note 44, at 70 (“Being surrounded by strangers at nighttime can also induce stress in people with mental health conditions.”). ↑
- See, e.g., Lu Zhao, Losing Things: Holding on to Possessions Is a Daily Struggle, with Deeper Symbolism, for Homeless People, Soc. Just. News Nexus (June 27, 2019), https://sjnnchicago.medill.northwestern.edu/blog/2019/06/27/losing-things-holding-on-to-possessions-is-a-daily-struggle-with-deeper-symbolism-for-homeless-people/ [https://perma.cc/68LA-ZN9K]. ↑
- See Rick Paulas, Encampment Sweeps Take Away People’s Most Important Belongings, Vice (Mar. 4, 2020), https://www.vice.com/en/article/v74pay/encampment-sweeps-take-away-homeless-peoples-most-important-belongings [https://perma.cc/SP3V-5KBY] (“[The police] give you 15 minutes to get what you want . . . ‘They ended up taking my birth certificate, my Social Security card, my mother’s necklace that her mother gave her, the only pictures of my brother and my dad, both of who are no longer here.’”). ↑
- Cf. id. (“Sometimes they lose tents or beds, or basic necessities like clothing or toiletries.”) ↑
- See Eve Garrow & Julia Devanthéry, “This Place Is Slowly Killing Me”: Abuse and Neglect in Orange County Emergency Shelters 67 (Mar. 2019), https://www.aclusocal.org/sites/default/files/aclu_socal_oc_shelters_report.pdf [https://perma.cc/4MK4-FJ2G] (“Residents are subjected to tolls when they come in to the shelter, the staff destroys or takes their belongings when they are evicted without notice, and the staff forces residents to throw away their property as a price of admission to shelter.”); Jessica Boehm, Garbage Bins and Zip Ties Create ‘Lifesaver’ Storage Program for Phoenix Homeless Population, AZ Central (Feb. 10, 2022), https://www.azcentral.com/story/news/local/phoenix/2022/02/10/phoenix-homelessness-new-storage-program-lifesaver/6585998001/ [https://perma.cc/9JF2-SGQH] (“Schwabenlender said many people miss appointments or refuse to stay in the shelter because there are limits on how many items they can bring inside.”); Jerusalem Demas, Los Angeles’s Quixotic Quest to End Homelessness, Vox (May 14, 2021), https://www.vox.com/22420753/homelessness-los-angeles-skid-row-judge-carter-housing-crisis-zoning [https://perma.cc/9NRJ-8G9T] (“Tars tells Vox that shelters frequently don’t allow homeless people to bring their possessions with them, even though they’re often the only items people have been able to keep safe since becoming homeless.”). ↑
- See Garrow & Devanthéry, supra note 321, at 67 (noting that staff forces residents to throw away their property as a price of admission to shelter). ↑
- N.Y.C. Dep’t of Homeless Servs., Statement of Client Rights and Client Code of Conduct 2, https://www.coalitionforthehomeless.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/07/DHS-Statement-of-Client-Rights-and-Client-Code-of-Conduct2009.pdf [https://perma.cc/N9GY-QJ6A]. ↑
- Onslow Cmty. Outreach, Inc., Homeless Shelter Standard Operating Procedures (2020), https://onslowco.org/sites/onslowco.org/files/Shelter%20Standard%20Operating%20Procedures.pdf [https://perma.cc/6PCK-TEMX]. ↑
- Rick Paulas, This Is Why Homeless People Don’t Go to Shelters, Vice (Feb. 24, 2020), https://www.vice.com/en/article/v74y3j/this-is-why-homeless-people-don’t-go-to-shelters [https://perma.cc/45ZC-LG2A]. ↑
- Id. (“Some shelter stays are for one night at a time, forcing people to leave when the sun comes up. Other shelters allow stays for longer periods, generally maxing out at around 90 days. But these spaces never provide a space you can truly call your own.”). ↑
- See Trevor Wilhelm, For Windsor’s Homeless, Taking Shelter Can Mean Leaving Belongings Behind, Windsor Star (Feb. 1, 2019), https://windsorstar.com/news/local-news/for-windsors-homeless-taking-shelter-can-mean-leaving-belongings-behind [https://perma.cc/B69X-XWFM] (“A tattered tarp, some old clothes and a grimy tin of shoe polish may not seem like much, but for John Rollo, they’re worth the risk of frostbite and hypothermia. Rollo, who has been living on the streets for several years, said many homeless people face a difficult decision when temperatures plunge: abandon their few belongings for a spot in a warm shelter, or freeze with them outside.”). ↑
- See Emma Woolley, How Many People Experiencing Homelessness Are Employed?, Homeless Hub (July 15, 2016), https://www.homelesshub.ca/blog/how-many-people-experiencing-homelessness-are-employed [https://perma.cc/C6HV-QJUQ] (“A 2013 story in The New York Times interviewed people working full-time jobs (sometimes more than one) and estimated that 28% of families experiencing homelessness included at least one working adult, and 16% of homeless individuals had jobs.”). ↑
- See, e.g., N.Y.C. Dep’t of Homeless Servs., Policy and Procedure No. AS 98-401, https://www.coalitionforthehomeless.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/07/control-and-confiscation-of-contraband-DHS-policy-AS-98-401.pdf [https://perma.cc/2EEF-TLCS] (listing the following as prohibited “contraband”: knives, sticks, bats, scissors, box cutters, sharpened tools or utensils, hammers, screwdrivers, and razors). ↑
- See, e.g., Thacher Schmid, Vehicle Residency: Homelessness We Struggle to Talk About, Nation (Nov. 11, 2021), https://www.thenation.com/article/society/homelessness-vehicle-residency-housing/ [https://perma.cc/M9XU-VZ6Y] (explaining that vehicle residents are “the nation’s fastest-growing homeless subpopulation”). ↑
- See, e.g., Paulas, supra note 325 (noting shelters in Oakland do not allow people with pets). ↑
- See Nick Kerman, What Can Be Done to Better Support People Experiencing Homelessness with Pets?, Homeless Hub (Dec. 1, 2020), https://www.homelesshub.ca/blog/what-can-be-done-better-support-people-experiencing-homelessness-pets [https://perma.cc/76KC-23BY] (“Given the strength of the human-animal bond and the importance of this relationship, it is perhaps unsurprising then that many pet owners say they ‘would never go’ to a shelter if they could not bring their animals.”). ↑
- Ari Shapiro, David Pritie, James Greene & Kathy Sibert, Why Some Homeless Choose the Streets over Shelters, NPR (Dec. 6, 2012), https://www.npr.org/2012/12/06/166666265/why-some-homeless-choose-the-streets-over-shelters [https://perma.cc/H2UH-UE6E]. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Jojola & Wilcox, supra note 285. ↑
- Emily Spence-Almaguer, Gabrianna Saks & Sandy Hogan, “It Happens Out Here”: The Victimization Experiences and Health Challenges of Women Who Are Homeless 16 (July 16, 2013), https://www.ahomewithhope.org/wp-content/uploads/HWHVS-Final-Report-to-the-Communityx.pdf [https://perma.cc/6RW7-DQEQ] (finding, in a study of 150 women, 22 percent stated that someone had stolen something from them outside, compared to almost 52 percent in a shelter). ↑
- See, e.g., Paulas, supra note 325. ↑
- See Emily Alpert Reyes, Benjamin Oreskes & Doug Smith, Why Did So Many Homeless People Die While Staying at One Hotel Used in Project Roomkey?, L.A. Times (June 28, 2021), https://www.latimes.com/homeless-housing/story/2021-06-28/la-homeless-people-died-after-entering-covid-hotel-why [https://perma.cc/TJ9B-CSJA] (“Orendorff said the clearing of encampments also broke up some of the familiar networks that people relied on for safety.”). ↑
- See Rebecca Cohen, Will Yetvin & Jill Khadduri, Understanding Encampments of People Experiencing Homelessness and Community Responses 5 (Jan. 7, 2019), https://www.huduser.gov/portal/sites/default/files/pdf/Understanding-Encampments.pdf [https://perma.cc/3WEU-UTMA] (“People who stay in encampments may see them as offering greater safety and protection . . . from assaults . . . than if they were unsheltered on their own. This sense of ‘safety in numbers’ may be particularly prevalent in long-standing and highly organized encampments, in which residents have established around-the-clock security patrols and mutually enforced norms and standards for behavior.”) (internal citations omitted). ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Why People Experiencing Homelessness Don’t Accept Shelter, Pallet (May 20, 2020), https://www.palletshelter.com/blog/2020/5/20/why-the-homeless-dont-accept-shelter [https://perma.cc/CA7W-YQXH] (“Every homeless encampment or gathering on the street is a community of its own with residents that look out for each other. For the homeless without family or a traditional support network, their fellow friends on the street act as their ‘family,’ and in some cases are their only safety net they have in times of trouble.”). ↑
- Micheal L. Shier, Marion E. Jones & John R. Graham, Social Communities and Homelessness: A Broader Concept Analysis of Social Relationships and Homelessness, 21 J. Hum. Behav. Soc. Env’t 455, 455 (2011). ↑
- Lisa M. Vandemark, Promoting the Sense of Self, Place, and Belonging in Displaced Persons: The Example of Homelessness, 21 Archives Psychiatric Nursing 241, 243 (2007). ↑
- Id. at 241–42. ↑
- Id. at 244–45. ↑
- See Stacy Rowe, Panhandlers and Sidewalk Encampments: Social Networks for the Homeless in Los Angeles, 11 Practicing Anthro. 14, 14 (1989). ↑
- Id. at 15. ↑
- See Cohen et al., supra note 339, at 4. ↑
- See Rowe, supra note 347, at 14. ↑
- Id. at 15. ↑
- See Rachel L. Rayburn & Jay Corzine, Your Shelter or Mine? Romantic Relationships Among the Homeless, 31 Deviant Behav. 756, 758 (2010) (noting that “[r]omantic relationships are one of the most important components of life satisfaction and well-being throughout a person’s life”); id. at 764 (“Some participants had been in relationships before they became homeless and were trying to work things out while they were living at the homeless shelter.”); id. at 766 (noting that for a woman who was not allowed to have male guests in her room at the women’s shelter, “she just spends the night at another shelter or a friend’s house when she wanted to [be sexually active].”). ↑
- See id. at 760 (“When individuals enter committed relationships, the way they exercise, go to the doctor, and eat change for the better.”). ↑
- Will You Still Be Mine? Couples Experiencing Homelessness, Substance Abuse & Mental Health Servs. Admin. (July 31, 2019), https://www.samhsa.gov/homelessness-programs-resources/hpr-resources/couples-experiencing-homelessness [https://perma.cc/BFY5-EXSM]. ↑
- NLCHP, Housing Not Handcuffs, supra note 44, at 34. ↑
- See Greg C. Cheyne, Facially Discriminatory Admissions Policies in Homeless Shelters and the Fair Housing Act, 1 U. Chi. Legal F. 459, 468 (2009) (noting how such policies may lead to “increase [of] the proportion of female headed households among homeless families,” the “dissolution of low-income families,” or the “plac[ing] [of] children in foster care”). ↑
- Caral Stevenson & Joanne Neale, ‘We Did More Rough Sleeping Just to Be Together’— Homeless Drug Users’ Romantic Relationships in Hostel Accommodation, 19 Drugs: Educ., Prevention & Pol’y, 234, 240 (2012). ↑
- Will You Still Be Mine? Couples Experiencing Homelessness, supra note 354. ↑
- See Stevenson & Neale, supra note 357, at 239. ↑
- Amy M. Donley & James D. Wright, Safer Outside: A Qualitative Exploration of Homeless People’s Resistance to Homeless Shelters, 12 J. Forensic Psych. Prac. 288, 299 (2012). ↑
- Namkee G. Choi & Lidia Snyder, Voices of Homeless Parents: The Pain of Homelessness and Shelter Life, 2 J. Hum. Behav. Soc. Env’t 55, 57 (2008). ↑
- Elizabeth R. Anthony, Aviva Vincent & Yoonkyung Shin, Parenting and Child Experiences in Shelter: A Qualitative Study Exploring the Effect of Homelessness on the Parent-Child Relationship, 23 Child & Fam. Soc. Work 8, 9 (2017). ↑
- See Becca Savransky, A Lot of Homeless People Referred to Shelters in Seattle Don’t Go. These Are Some Reasons Why, Seattle PI, (Oct. 10, 2019), https://www.seattlepi.com/homeless_in_seattle/article/A-lot-of-homeless-people-the-city-refers-to-14504490.php [https://perma.cc/9XJ6-KP92]. ↑
- Choi & Snyder, supra note 361. ↑
- See Marybeth Shinn, Jessica Gibbons-Benton & Scott R. Brown, Poverty, Homelessness, and Family Break‑Up, 94 Child Welfare 105, 105 (2015). ↑
- See id. at 112–13. ↑
- Anthony, Vincent & Shin, supra note 362, at 11. ↑
- Id. at 12 (“Several mothers talked about how their children lost weight while staying at the shelter: ‘. . . he barely ate their food because, I don’t know, it would give him the runs, and so yeah, so he lost a lot of weight.’”). ↑
- Id. ↑
- In recent years, some homelessness advocates have advanced a similar idea under the rubric of a “right to rest.” See Heather Marek, Katie Sawicki, Zoe La Du, Corrine Fletcher, Elena Stross & Franz Bruggemeier, Decriminalizing Homelessness: Why Right to Rest Legislation Is the High Road for Oregon 23 (2017), https://aclu-or.org/sites/default/files/field_documents/aclu-decriminalizing-homelessness_full-report_web_final.pdf [https://perma.cc/Q63R-PTCS] (explaining that a right to rest would ideally include the rights of homeless individuals to “(1) move freely and sleep in public spaces without discrimination, (2) sleep in a parked vehicle, (3) eat and exchange food in public, and (4) have 24-hour access to hygiene facilities”). To date, however, efforts to legislate a right to rest have fallen far short of a true right to self-shelter in public spaces. See, e.g., H.B. 3115, 81st Leg., Reg. Sess. (Or. 2021) (permitting homeless individuals an affirmative defense in prosecutions for urban camping if the law is “not objectively reasonable”). ↑
- Although the word “dignity” does not appear in the due process clauses of either the Fifth or Fourteenth Amendments, the Supreme Court’s recent due process jurisprudence has identified human dignity as a core value protected by those clauses. See infra Part IV.A. ↑
- See Christopher McCrudden, In Pursuit of Human Dignity: An Introduction to Current Debates, in Understanding Human Dignity 1, 8–10 (Christopher McCrudden ed., 2013) (reviewing scholars’ theories of dignity). ↑
- See Jeremy Waldron, Dignity, Rank, & Rights 212 (Meir Dan-Cohen ed., 2012). ↑
- See Leslie Meltzer Henry, The Jurisprudence of Dignity, 160 U. Pa. L. Rev. 169, 178 (2011). ↑
- See infra Part IV.A. ↑
- **539 U.S. 558 (2003). ↑
- Laurence H. Tribe, Equal Dignity: Speaking Its Name, 129 Harv. L. Rev. F. 16, 17 (2015). ↑
- Brief of Petitioners, Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) (No. 02-102), 2003 WL 152352, at *23 & n.17 (collecting case law repealing sodomy laws after Bowers). ↑
- See Pew Rsch. Ctr., Religious Beliefs Underpin Opposition to Homosexuality 1–3 (Nov. 18, 2003), https://www.pewresearch.org/politics/2003/11/18/religious-beliefs-underpin-opposition-to-homosexuality/ [https://perma.cc/L2SM-M6SM] (concluding that, while the public had shifted from the 1980s and now widely opposed discrimination against same-sex couples, backlash was growing). ↑
- Andrew R. Flores, National Trends in Public Opinion on LGBT Rights in the United States 10, 15 (2014), https://williamsinstitute.law.ucla.edu/wp-content/uploads/Public-Opinion-LGBT-US-Nov-2014.pdf [https://perma.cc/4W47-J7Q8]. ↑
- Tom W. Smith, Cross-National Differences in Attitudes Towards Homosexuality 19 (Apr. 2011), https://gss.norc.org/Documents/reports/cross-national-reports/CNR%2031.pdf [https://perma.cc/3HBP-7M6P] (reporting results from the International Social Survey Program). ↑
- See Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186, 196 (1986). ↑
- Dale Carpenter, The Unknown Past of Lawrence v. Texas, 102 Mich. L. Rev. 1464, 1477 (2004) ↑
- Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 562 (2003). ↑
- Id. at 563. But see Carpenter, supra note 383, at 1478–91 (detailing the conflicting accounts of the arrests, and reasoning that officers were unlikely to have witnessed the sex acts at issue). ↑
- Lawrence v. State, 41 S.W.3d 349, 350 (Tex. App. 2001), rev’d, 539 U.S. 558 (2003). ↑
- See Katherine Franke, Comment, The Domesticated Liberty of Lawrence v. Texas, 104 Colum. L. Rev. 1339, 1401 (2004) (“While it was widely expected that the Court would find the Texas sodomy law unconstitutional, the sweeping—indeed moving—language that Justice Kennedy uses in the majority’s opinion came as quite a surprise.”). ↑
- See Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 564. ↑
- Id. at 579–85 (O’Connor, J., concurring). ↑
- Brief of Petitioners, supra note 378, at 9 (arguing that governments ought not to be policing private bedrooms given Griswold v. Connecticut and Eisenstadt v. Baird*). ↑
- Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 562. ↑
- Id. at 578. ↑
- See Laurence H. Tribe, Lawrence v. Texas: The “Fundamental Right” That Dare Not Speak Its Name, 117 Harv. L. Rev. 1893, 1905 (2004) (explaining that allowing the state the power to regulate sexual relationships “would have drained those relationships of their unique significance as expressions of self-government”). ↑
- See Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 565–67. ↑
- See Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 703 (1997). ↑
- Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 578 (“The Texas statute furthers no legitimate state interest which can justify its intrusion into the personal and private life of the individual.”). ↑
- See id. at 586 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (“Most of the rest of today’s opinion has no relevance to its actual holding—that the Texas statute ‘furthers no legitimate state interest which can justify’ its application to petitioners under rational-basis review.”). ↑
- Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186, 191–92 (1986). ↑
- Tribe, supra note 393, at 1898–99. ↑
- Id. at 1899. ↑
- Gregory S. Alexander, Property, Dignity, and Human Flourishing, 104 Cornell L. Rev. 991, 1005 (2019). ↑
- Lawrence’s vision of liberty was admittedly less liberal than some scholars of gender and sexuality had hoped. Noting that the opinion emphasized personal relationships, rather than sexual activity, Professor Katherine Franke described the liberty principle articulated as “less expansive, rather geographized, and, in the end, domesticated.” Franke, supra note 387, at 1401. ↑
- Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 567; cf. Roberts v. U.S. Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609, 617–18 (1984) (“[C]hoices to enter into and maintain certain intimate human relationships must be secured against undue intrusion by the State because of the role of such relationships in safeguarding the individual freedom that is central to our constitutional scheme.”). ↑
- Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 567. ↑
- Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965). ↑
- Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 564. ↑
- Griswold, 381 U.S. at 485. ↑
- Id. at 480. ↑
- Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972). ↑
- Id. at 453. Arguably, that liberty interest reached its apex in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992), since overruled by Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Organization, No. 19-1392, 597 U.S. __ (June 24, 2022). In Casey, the Court explained that both the decision to carry a child to term and the decision to terminate a pregnancy involve physical and emotional burdens that are “too intimate and too personal for the State to insist, without more, upon its own vision of the woman’s role.” 505 U.S. at 852. Indeed, the Casey Court famously proclaimed, “[a]t the heart of liberty is the right to define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life.” Id. at 851. Although the current Court has since rejected the view that the right to terminate a pregnancy is “fundamental,” a faithful recounting of the Lawrence decision must acknowledge the role that this precedent played in constructing the case for the decriminalization of sodomy. See Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 574 (quoting Casey’s “mystery of human life” passage at length). ↑
- Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 575 (2003). ↑
- Id. ↑
- This commitment to substantive equality mirrors the work of Professor Catherine MacKinnon elsewhere. See, e.g., Catharine A. MacKinnon, Substantive Equality: A Perspective, 96 Minn. L. Rev. 1 (2011). ↑
- Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 575. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Tribe, supra note 393, at 1898–99. ↑
- Id. at 1898. ↑
- See Reva B. Siegel, Dignity and the Politics of Protection: Abortion Restrictions under Casey/Carhart, 117 Yale L.J. 1694, 1696 (2008); Rebecca L. Brown, Liberty, the New Equality, 77 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1491, 1506–08 (2002); Kenji Yoshino, The New Equal Protection, 124 Harv. L. Rev. 747, 749 (2011). ↑
- Yoshino, supra note 418, at 749–50. ↑
- United States v. Windsor, 570 U.S. 744, 775 (2013) (“The federal statute is invalid, for no legitimate purpose overcomes the purpose and effect to disparage and to injure those whom the State, by its marriage laws, sought to protect in personhood and dignity.”). ↑
- Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S. 644, 681 (2015) (“They ask for equal dignity in the eyes of the law. The Constitution grants them that right.”). ↑
- Windsor, 570 U.S. at 768. ↑
- Id. at 769. ↑
- See id. at 746. ↑
- Id. at 774. ↑
- Obergefell, 576 U.S. at 663. ↑
- Id. at 660; see also id. at 660–61 (“[T]he argument that gays and lesbians had a just claim to dignity was in conflict with both law and widespread social conventions.”). ↑
- Id. at 666–67. ↑
- See Kenji Yoshino, A New Birth of Freedom?: Obergefell v. Hodges, 129 Harv. L. Rev. 147, 172, 174 (2015); see also Obergefell, 576 U.S. at 673. ↑
- Masterpiece Cakeshop, Ltd. v. Colo. C.R. Comm’n, 138 S. Ct. 1719, 1727 (2018). ↑
- Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186, 190 (1986). ↑
- Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 567 (2003). ↑
- Id. at 564. ↑
- See id. ↑
- Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 777 (1997) (Souter, J., concurring) (internal citation omitted). ↑
- See Rochin v. California, 342 U.S. 165, 173 (1952) (holding that due process was violated when police directed a doctor to pump the defendant’s stomach to retrieve evidence of drug use). ↑
- Cruzan v. Dir., Mo. Dep’t of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 278 (1990) (“The principle that a competent person has a constitutionally protected liberty interest in refusing unwanted medical treatment may be inferred from our prior decisions.”); Washington v. Harper, 494 U.S. 210, 229 (1990) (“The forcible injection of medication into a nonconsenting person’s body represents a substantial interference with that person’s liberty.”); Vitek v. Jones, 445 U.S. 480, 494 (1980) (transferring a person to a mental hospital coupled with mandatory behavior modification treatment implicated liberty interests); Parham v. J.R., 442 U.S. 584, 600 (1979) (“[A] child, in common with adults, has a substantial liberty interest in not being confined unnecessarily for medical treatment.”). ↑
- Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 567. ↑
- Id. at 573–74. ↑
- No. 19-1392, 597 U.S. __ (June 24, 2022). ↑
- As numerous commentators have noted, Justice Alito’s opinion in Dobbs should not properly be considered “originalist,” despite its emphasis on history and tradition. See, e.g., Ilan Wurman, Opinion: Hard to Square Dobbs and Bruen with Originalism, Denver Post (July 12, 2022), https://www.denverpost.com/2022/07/12/roe-vs-wade-originalism-dobbs-bruen-abortion-guns/ [https://perma.cc/87XD-JV5V]; Cass Sunstein, The Alito Draft (May 23, 2022) (preliminary draft), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4117446 [https://perma.cc/6N57-9SE9]. ↑
- Dobbs, No. 19-1392, slip op. at 5 (quoting Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 702, 721 (1997)) (emphasis added). ↑
- Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 572 (quoting County of Sacramento v. Lewis, 523 U.S. 833, 857 (1998) (Kennedy, J., concurring) (internal quotation marks omitted)). ↑
- See, e.g., Leslie J. Reagan, What Alito Gets Wrong About the History of Abortion in America, Politico (June 2, 2022), https://www.politico.com/news/magazine/2022/06/02/alitos-anti-roe-argument-wrong-00036174 [https://perma.cc/6BP3-Q9AL]; Lawrence Hurley, Alito’s Abortion History Lesson in Dispute, Reuters (May 6, 2022), https://www.reuters.com/legal/government/us-supreme-court-justice-alitos-abortion-history-lesson-dispute-2022-05-06/ [https://perma.cc/GPG8-BAQR]; Gillian Brockell, Abortion in the Founders’ Era: Violent, Chaotic, and Unregulated, Wash. Post (May 15, 2022), https://www.washingtonpost.com/history/2022/05/15/abortion-history-founders-alito/ [https://perma.cc/87AT-NPQK]. ↑
- See Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 572 (citing an “emerging awareness that liberty gives substantial protection to adult persons in deciding how to conduct their private lives in matters pertaining to sex”). Note that Justice Alito quite explicitly challenges this approach to jurisprudence, claiming that recognizing “a broader right to autonomy” “could license fundamental rights to illicit drug use, prostitution, and the like.” Dobbs, No. 19-1392, slip op. at 32. ↑
- See e.g., Kathryn Rubino, The Supreme Court Has Only Scratched the Surface of Awful, Above the Law (May 3, 2022), https://abovethelaw.com/2022/05/the-supreme-court-has-only-scratched-the-surface-of-awful/ [https://perma.cc/GXM7-KQX4]. ↑
- Dobbs, No. 19-1392, slip op. at 66 (“Nothing in this opinion should be understood to cast doubt on precedents that do not concern abortion.”). ↑
- Id. at 32. ↑
- See id. at 32–33 (quoting Casey, 505 U.S. at 848) (internal quotation marks omitted). ↑
- Id. at 5 (Breyer, J., Sotomayor, J., and Kagan, J., dissenting). ↑
- See Note, Equal Dignity—Heeding Its Call, 132 Harv. L. Rev. 1323, 1329 (2019). ↑
- See supra text accompanying notes 401–06, 431–33. ↑
- See, e.g., Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 57–79. ↑
- See, e.g., Cruzan v. Dir., Mo. Dep’t of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 278 (1990). ↑
- Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609, 617–18 (1984). ↑
- Id. at 619. ↑
- See supra text accompanying notes 337–69. ↑
- Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497, 543 (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting from dismissal on jurisdictional grounds). ↑
- Reva Siegel, Reasoning from the Body: A Historical Perspective on Abortion Regulation and Questions of Equal Protection, 44 Stan. L. Rev. 261, 353 (1992). Kenji Yoshino has similarly described the Court’s more recent cases as articulating a vision of “antisubordination liberty.” See Yoshino, supra note 429, at 174. ↑
- Siegel, supra note 459, at 353. ↑
- See Yoshino, supra note 429, at 174–75 (“What Obergefell does is to drive this idea further to the surface—asserting that in the common law adjudication of new liberties, the effect on those subordinated groups should matter.”). ↑
- Equal Dignity, supra note 451, at 1334. ↑
- See supra notes 49–63 and accompanying text. ↑
- See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 575 (2003); Tribe, supra note 393, at 1896, 1910–14 (explaining how the Lawrence decision recognized that the “social and cultural meaning of the ban on sodomy operates to deny the equal worth and equal liberty” of same-sex couples). ↑
- Tribe, supra note 393, at 1896. ↑
- See Cass R. Sunstein, What Did Lawrence Hold? Of Autonomy, Desuetude, Sexuality, and Marriage, 2003 Sup. Ct. Rev. 27, 49 (“These points suggest that the Court’s decision was less about sexual autonomy, as a freestanding idea, and closer to a kind of due process variation on the old common law idea of desuetude.”). ↑
- See, e.g., Mortimer R. Kadish & Sanford H. Kadish, Discretion to Disobey: A Study of Lawful Departures from Legal Rules 129–31 (1973). ↑
- Sunstein, supra note 466, at 49–50 (citing Griswold v. Connecticut as another example of desuetude). ↑
- Id. at 50. ↑
- See id. at 49 (“A simple autonomy reading would have consequences that the Court did not likely intend.”). ↑
- Id. (citing incest and bestiality as examples). ↑
- Id. at 50. ↑
- See supra notes 76–77 and accompanying text. ↑
- See supra note 85 and accompanying text. ↑
- Id. at 50. ↑
- Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 560 (2003). But see id. at 562 (describing “other spheres of our lives and existence, outside the home, where the State should not be a dominant presence”). ↑
- See id. at 574, 588 (explaining that “[p]ersons in a homosexual relationship may seek autonomy” for purposes that include “the right to define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life”) (quoting Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 851 (1992)). ↑
- See Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 447 n.7 (1972) (“Of course, if we were to conclude that the Massachusetts statute impinges upon fundamental freedoms . . . the statutory classification would have to be not merely rationally related to a valid public purpose, but necessary to the achievement of a compelling state interest.”). ↑
- Stuart P. Green, To See and Be Seen: Reconstructing the Law of Voyeurism and Exhibitionism, 55 Am. Crim. L. Rev. 203, 211 (2018) (emphasis in original). ↑
- Lior Jacob Strahilevitz, Consent, Aesthetics, and the Boundaries of Sexual Privacy After Lawrence v. Texas, 54 DePaul L. Rev. 671, 689–90 (2005). ↑
- See Lawrence M. Friedman & Joanna L. Grossman, A Private Underworld: The Naked Body in Law and Society, 61 Buff. L. Rev. 169, 174, 180 (2013) (distinguishing between simple nudity and lewd nudity, the latter of which is “overtly sexual, and is thought of as perverse, or threatening”). ↑
- Id. at 207. This view is shared by such thinkers as John Stuart Mill and H.L.A. Hart. See John Stuart Mill, On Liberty 90 (Batoche Books 2001) (1859) (“Of this kind are offenses against decency; on which it is unnecessary to dwell, the rather as they are only connected indirectly with our subject, the objection to publicity being equally strong in the case of many actions not in themselves condemnable, nor supposed to be so.”); H.L.A. Hart, Law, Liberty, and Morality 45 (1963) (“Sexual intercourse between husband and wife is not immoral, but if it takes place in public it is an affront to public decency.”). ↑
- See Rankin, supra note 98, at 589; see generally Foscarinis et al., supra note 96 (surveying criminal laws designed to reduce the visibility of homelessness without addressing root causes). ↑
- See Rankin, supra note 98, at 568 (“If constituents can literally ‘see’ changes in unsheltered homelessness on the street, they are more likely to support investments in solutions for homelessness broadly.”). ↑
- See, e.g., Cal. Penal Code §§ 647(a), 647(c)–(f). Such laws may also include existing on private property—even if one just wanders upon it. See Cal. Penal Code § 647(h). ↑
- Professor Dorothy Roberts has argued that the vague definitions of acceptable purposes in loitering laws “incorporate[] racist notions of criminality and legitimate[] police harassment of Black citizens.” Dorothy E. Roberts, Foreword: Race, Vagueness, and the Social Meaning of Order-Maintenance Policing, 89 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 775, 790 (1999). ↑
- L.A., Cal. Mun. Code § 85.02 (regulating the use of vehicles for dwelling). This provision imposed a blanket prohibition on sleeping in vehicles dating back to 1983, Desertrain v. City of Los Angeles, 754 F.3d 1147, 1149 (9th Cir. 2014), but was recently amended following a successful vagueness challenge. See id. at 1157. ↑
- See Rankin, supra note 7, at 122–23 (“These deeply rooted ‘psychological mechanisms’ compel us to prevent contact with homeless people because we implicitly associate them with disease, perceiving them as ‘pathogenic threats’ we must avoid through ‘physical distancing’ to avoid potential contamination.”); see also Rankin, supra note 98, at 584 (“Studies show that humans react to traditional markers of unsheltered chronic homelessness with unparalleled rates of negativity and disgust, which may become even more pronounced when the stigma of homelessness inevitability intersects with other prejudices.”); cf. Mayor of New York v. Miln, 36 U.S. 102, 142 (1837) (announcing that it is “as competent and as necessary for a state to provide precautionary measures against the moral pestilence of paupers, vagabonds, and possibly convicts; as it is to guard against physical pestilence”). ↑
- See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 570 (2003) (explaining that criminalization of same-sex sodomy was primarily motivated by centuries-old moral condemnation of the practice). ↑
- Id. at 572 (quoting County of Sacramento v. Lewis, 523 U.S. 833, 857 (1998)). ↑
- Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S. 644, 671–72 (2015). ↑
- See Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 578 (“The Texas statute furthers no legitimate state interest which can justify its intrusion into the personal and private life of the individual.”); see also Robin Yeamans, Constitutional Attacks on Vagrancy Laws, 20 Stan. L. Rev. 782, 784–85 (1968) (“[W]here the offense consists merely in being idle, indigent, or itinerant, as in most statutes that retain in some form the common-law crime of vagrancy, the legitimacy of the state’s interest in imposing criminal sanctions is not clear.”) ↑
- Although public urination or defecation less obviously harm third parties and may be necessarily connected to the protected conduct of self-sheltering, I nevertheless acknowledge that dignity in the constitutional sense—rather than the moral sense—may not extend far enough to decriminalize these behaviors. See infra notes 523–528 and accompanying text. ↑
- In 1922, the U.S. “Commerce Department promulgated the Standard Zoning Enabling Act,” intended as model authorizing legislation for states to empower local government zoning. Christopher Serkin, A Case for Zoning, 96 Notre Dame L. Rev. 749, 755 (2020). In 1926, the Supreme Court upheld the practice of local zoning against a constitutional attack. See Vill. of Euclid v. Ambler Realty Co., 272 U.S. 365, 397 (1926). ↑
- Serkin, supra note 494, at 758. ↑
- Berman v. Parker, 348 U.S. 26, 33 (1954) (“It is within the power of the legislature to determine that the community should be beautiful as well as healthy, spacious as well as clean, well-balanced as well as carefully patrolled.”). ↑
- Moore v. City of East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494, 506 (1977) (plurality opinion). ↑
- Id. at 496. ↑
- Id. at 499–500. ↑
- See Angela Onwuachi-Willig, Extending the Normativity of the Extended Family: Reflections on Moore v. City of East Cleveland, 85 Fordham L. Rev. 2655, 2659 (2017) (“Justice Brennan’s concurrence became the subject of longstanding praise in legal academia because it acknowledged how notions of family can be raced and classed.”). ↑
- Moore, 431 U.S. at 507 (Brennan, J., concurring). ↑
- Id. at 508. ↑
- See, e.g., Doe v. Miller, 405 F.3d 700, 710 (8th Cir. 2005) (“Thus, the reasoning of the Moore plurality does not require strict scrutiny of a regulation that has an incidental or unintended effect on the family . . . or that ‘affects or encourages decisions on family matters’ but does not force such choices.”). ↑
- State v. Seering, 701 N.W.2d 655, 663 (Iowa 2005). ↑
- See Miller, 405 F.3d at 710. ↑
- Id. at 710; see also Weems v. Little Rock Police Dep’t, 453 F.3d 1010, 1014–15 (8th Cir. 2006) (holding that sex offender residency restrictions do not unconstitutionally violate substantive due process, equal protection, or the fundamental right to travel). ↑
- Mary Kay Thill, Zoning out the Homeless People, Nw. Compass (Apr. 1, 2017), https://northwestcompass.org/zoning-homeless-people/ [https://perma.cc/3CKJ-B9JQ]. ↑
- See, e.g., Egon Bittner, The Police on Skid-Row: A Study of Peace Keeping, 32 Am. Socio. Rev. 699, 704 (1967); see also Charles Hoch & Robert A. Slayton, New Homeless and Old: Community and the Skid Row Hotel 105 (1989) (“[T]he job of the patrolman was primarily to maintain the spatial order by seeing that the accepted boundaries of Skid Row were maintained. This was done by confining the men to their specific neighborhood and prohibiting spillover into middle-class sections.”) (internal quotations omitted). But see Nicole Stelle Garnett, Relocating Disorder, 91 Va. L. Rev. 1075, 1102 (2005) (“As skid row declined, however, police officers, faced with more severe social deviancy and greater societal hostility, felt pressure to exercise a greater amount of control within skid row as well.”). ↑
- See Garnett, supra note 508, at 1085–88 (discussing the phenomenon of homeless campuses). ↑
- See Serkin, supra note 494, at 758 (explaining that, under the Standard Zoning Enabling Act, zoning ordinances must be part of a comprehensive city plan). ↑
- See Lee Anne Fennell, Properties of Concentration, 73 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1227, 1227 (2006) (explaining how concentrated poverty has negative effects on education, safety, and children). ↑
- See, e.g., Serkin, supra note 494, at 754–60. ↑
- Foscarinis et al., supra note 96, at 147 n.2. ↑
- Many years ago, Professor Robert Ellickson suggested that zoning laws should be used to concentrate disorder, including homelessness, into specifically designated public spaces akin to skid rows. Robert C. Ellickson, Controlling Chronic Misconduct in City Spaces: Of Panhandlers, Skid Rows, and Public Space Zoning, 105 Yale L.J. 1165, 1220–23 (1996). ↑
- See, e.g., Papachristou v. City of Jacksonville, 405 U.S. 156, 169 (1972) (“Future criminality, however, is the common justification for the presence of vagrancy statutes.”). ↑
- Roberts, supra note 486, at 783 (examining loitering laws as a prophylactic measure to fight crime and maintain public order). ↑
- Compare Randeep Ramesh, A Fifth of All Homeless People Have Committed a Crime to Get off the Streets, Guardian (Dec. 22, 2010), https://www.theguardian.com/society/2010/dec/23/homeless-committing-crimes-for-shelter [https://perma.cc/YFK4-YKYN], with Thacher Schmid, No Link. Between Homeless Villages and Crime Rates, Guardian Review Suggests, Guardian (May 23, 2018), https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2018/may/23/homeless-villages-crime-rate-seattle-portland [https://perma.cc/J5V9-UD42]. See generally John J. Ammann, Addressing Quality of Life Crimes in Our Cities: Criminalization, Community Courts and Community Compassion, 44 St. Louis U. L.J. 811, 815 (2000) (“While the current effort in cities focuses on prosecution of the homeless for their crimes, it is, in fact, the poor and homeless who are more likely to be the victims of crime than they are to be the criminals.”). ↑
- See Sara Shortt, We Don’t Need Protection from the Homeless. They Need Protection from Us, L.A. Times (Oct. 15, 2018), https://www.latimes.com/opinion/op-ed/la-oe-shortt-homeless-victims-20181015-story.html [https://perma.cc/S8E5-Y453]. ↑
- Anya Zoledziowski, Homeless People Have Nowhere to Go to the Bathroom Because of Coronavirus, Vice (Apr. 8, 2020), https://www.vice.com/en/article/dygqna/homeless-people-have-next-to-zero-bathrooms-because-of-coronavirus [https://perma.cc/4GTU-Z2CV]. ↑
- See Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 447 n.7 (1972). ↑
- See, e.g., New York v. Ferber, 458 U.S. 747, 756–57 (1982). ↑
- Although drug use does not, alone, implicate third-party harms, some members of the Supreme Court have indicated that it is a sufficiently serious criminal matter to qualify as a “compelling” interest. See Emp. Div., Dep’t of Hum. Res. of Or. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 904–05 (1990) (O’Connor, J., concurring). Individuals experiencing homelessness are often stigmatized as drug users, saddled with the unstated implication that drug use is a primary cause of their homelessness, a barrier to escaping homelessness, or both. See, e.g., Melanie B. Abbott, Homelessness and Substance Abuse: Is Mandatory Treatment the Solution?, 22 Fordham Urb. L.J. 1, 2 (1994). While homeless individuals experience drug and alcohol abuse at roughly twice the rate of housed individuals, see Rankin, supra note 7, at 105, it is the criminal response to drug use that most threatens the security of homeless drug users. An emerging consensus recognizes the failures of American drug policy. see Glenn Greenwald, Drug Decriminalization in Portugal: Lessons for Creating Fair & Successful Drug Policies (2009), https://www.tni.org/files/publication-downloads/greenwald_whitepaper.pdf [https://perma.cc/VW4G-ACLN]; see generally Glob. Comm’n on Drug Pol’y, Time to End Prohibition 7–11 (2021), https://www.globalcommissionondrugs.org/wp-content/uploads/2021/12/Time_to_end_prohibition_EN_2021_report.pdf [https://perma.cc/DF7R-43W7] (bolstering the consensus with the examples of countries that have decriminalized drug use). ↑
- See, e.g., Ron S. Hochbaum, Bathrooms as a Homeless Rights Issue, 98 N.C. L. Rev. 205, 234 (2020) (“In the United States, and much of the Western world, the ability to use the bathroom in private is synonymous with dignity.”). ↑
- See supra notes 471–476, and accompanying text. ↑
- See Strahilevitz, supra note 480, at 689–90; see also Carlos A. Ball, Privacy, Property, and Public Sex, 18 Colum. J. Gender & L. 1, 13 (2008) (“[T]hose who do not want to observe the sex in question—individuals whom we can refer to as ‘unwilling gazers’—have a legitimate interest in not having sex thrust upon them.”). ↑
- See People v. McDonald, 40 Cal. Rptr. 3d 422, 434–35 (Cal. Ct. App. 2006) (discussing justifications for laws against public urination and defecation). ↑
- Hochbaum, supra note 523, at 236. ↑
- An interesting possibility is that such activities, while not decriminalized as a violation of Due Process, may be protected by the Eighth Amendment as involuntary incidents of the status of homelessness when inadequate public restrooms are provided by the state. ↑
- Meanwhile, those of us who fear that the policing of these crimes will continue to be disproportionately directed at homeless populations must embrace the reality that there will be more work to do to truly ensure the dignity of these populations. ↑
- See, e.g., Kevin Bundy, “Officer, Where’s My Stuff?”: The Constitutional Implications of a De Facto Property Disability for Homeless People, 1 Hastings Race & Poverty L.J. 57, 59 (2003). ↑
- See Andrée Tremoulet, Ellen Bassett & Allison Moe, Homeless Encampments on Public Right-of-Way: A Planning and Best Practices Guide (2012), https://ppms.trec.pdx.edu/media/137530914651f98d5a443e9.pdf [https://perma.cc/N9VB-Z3VB]; Anna Maria Barry-Jester, Sweeps of Homeless Camps in California Aggravate Key Health Issues, NPR (Jan. 10, 2020), https://www.npr.org/sections/health-shots/2020/01/10/794616155/sweeps-of-homeless-camps-in-california-aggravate-key-health-issues [https://perma.cc/TV98-T44K]. ↑
- Elizabeth Chou, LA Activists, Public Health Experts Fear Revived Encampment Sweeps Could Spread Coronavirus, L.A. Daily News (Sept. 10, 2021), https://www.dailynews.com/2021/09/10/l-a-activists-public-health-experts-fear-revived-encampment-sweeps-could-spread-coronavirus/ [https://perma.cc/KD7Y-AJSS] (detailing the spread of COVID-19within homeless encampments). ↑
- Benjamin Oreskes & David Zahniser, Minority of Sanitation Workers Report Being Vaccinated, Worrying Homeless Advocates, L.A. Times (Sept. 30, 2021), https://www.latimes.com/homeless-housing/story/2021-09-30/la-doesnt-know-if-most-sanitation-works-are-vaccinated-but-theyre-still-cleaning-encampments [https://perma.cc/K9TQ-4MF5] (explaining the sanitation justification for encampment sweeps in Los Angeles). ↑
- Nadra Nittle, Surprise Homeless Sweeps Aren’t Just Disruptive, Say Activists—They Aren’t Working, Curbed L.A. (Apr. 26, 2019), https://la.curbed.com/2019/4/25/18516026/homeless-sweeps-encampments-clean-streets [https://perma.cc/7BSK-SQTV] (explaining that one justification for encampment sweeps in Los Angeles is to remove sidewalk obstructions in order to maintain compliance with the Americans with Disabilities Act). ↑
- Rankin, supra note 98, at 590–91 (“By justifying sweeps as necessary for public health or safety, cities attempt to distinguish such practices from the criminal punishment Martin rejects.”). ↑
- Paulas, supra note 319. ↑
- Cities, however, should be mindful that encampment sweeps may arguably violate due process to the extent that they put homeless individuals at increased risk of danger, such as from extreme weather conditions. See Sanchez v. City of Fresno, 914 F. Supp. 2d 1079, 1102 (E.D. Cal. 2012). ↑
- Rankin, supra note 98, at 593–94. ↑
- Id. at 594. ↑
- See, e.g., Jessica Boehm, Homeless Encampment Cleanups in DOJ Probe Were Unanimously Approved by Phoenix City Council, AZ Central (Sept. 8, 2021), https://www.azcentral.com/story/news/local/phoenix/2021/09/08/phoenix-doj-investigation-homeless-camp-cleanups-were-unanimously-approved/5572425001 [https://perma.cc/FV7S-DTKB] (detailing a Department of Justice investigation into Phoenix encampment sweeps); Paulas, supra note 319 (noting a class action lawsuit challenging Los Angeles sweeps). ↑
- See Foscarinis et al., supra note 96, at 156 (“Government policies that attempt to ‘sweep’ homeless people from public areas are quick-fix measures offered by politicians in response to pressure from a vocal minority of businesses or residents to ‘do something’ about homelessness.”). ↑
DOI: https://doi.org/10.15779/Z38ZC7RV8T.
Copyright © 2023 Ben A. McJunkin, Associate Professor of Law, Sandra Day O’Connor College of Law at Arizona State University; Associate Deputy Director, Academy for Justice. I am deeply indebted to a number of generous commentators, including Chinonso Anozie, Laura Coordes, Kip Hustace, Kaiponanea Matsumura, Sara Rankin, Joshua Sellers, Bijal Shah, Erin Scharff, Michael Serota, and Ilan Wurman, as well as the participants of the Arizona State University Faculty Colloquium. I am immensely grateful for research assistance from Grace Duval, Joanna Jandali, Krysta Polakowski, and Kaylee Racs, as well as terrific editorial assistance from Samuel Charles, Arni Daroy, and the student editors at the California Law Review.