Regulating Offensiveness: Snyder v. Phelps, Emotion, and the First Amendment
Since 2005, the Reverend Fred Phelps and other members of the Westboro Baptist Church have outraged almost everyone by protesting near military funerals.
This case, however, has the potential to undo decades of the Court’s jurisprudence protecting offensive speech. Nothing about Snyder suggests that the Phelps disrupted the funeral.
Psychological research on emotions validates the Court’s approach by revealing that anger—the emotion most likely involved with speech we find offensive—is inextricably linked to censorship. Put simply, individuals get angry when others demean their personal or social identities.
The Court’s requirement of external indicia of harm, such as imminent violence, intuitively recognizes and protects against our subjective and unpredictable emotional responses to speech. Absent an external constraint, allowing anger or outrage to guide regulation of speech leads to suppression of speech simply because the content offends a listener’s world view. Unfortunately, the arguments made in favor of tort liability in Snyder effectively bypass such external indicia by asking the Court to allow tort liability based on little more than the Phelps’ offensive messages.
Part I of this essay discusses the history of Snyder. Part II examines the Court’s doctrines pertaining to offensive speech, reviewing its longstanding jurisprudence protecting offensive messages and explaining why the Phelps’ speech in Snyder fits within this doctrine. Part III then examines certain exceptions to the Court’s protection of speech, the captive audience and low value speech doctrines, and explains why attempts to analogize between these doctrines and the tort liability in Snyder fall short. Finally, Part IV discusses the psychology of emotions, focusing primarily on how anger arises. Relying on these psychological findings, Part IV explains why Snyder’s intentional infliction of emotional distress (IIED) and invasion of privacy claims cannot fit within the existing free speech structure. The article concludes that the Court should not recognize a claim for IIED based on offensive messages like those involved in Snyder as such liability risks undermining decades of the Court’s free speech jurisprudence and chilling protected speech.
Table of Contents Show
I. Snyder v. Phelps—Background
A. The Facts
The Phelps started protesting at the funerals of slain Iraqi and Afghan war veterans in 2005 to spread their belief that those wars were the ultimate result of America’s willingness to embrace homosexuality.
Snyder, however, involves a civil suit stemming from the Phelps’ protest near the funeral of Snyder’s son, Lance Corporal Matthew Snyder. After issuing a press release and notifying local police about their intent to picket the funeral, seven members of Phelps’ congregation, the Westboro Baptist Church, protested at Matthew Snyder’s funeral with signs bearing messages similar or identical to those described above.
The Phelps also posted an Internet “epic” on their website mentioning Snyder and his son.
B. The Lawsuit
Snyder sued the Phelps for IIED and invasion of privacy/intrusion upon seclusion in 2007.
The Fourth Circuit Court of Appeals, however, found that the First Amendment protected the Phelps’ speech. Although recognizing that the expression profoundly distressed Snyder, the appellate court ruled that tort liability was inappropriate when speech “cannot reasonably be interpreted as stating actual facts about an individual.”
The Supreme Court granted certiorari in March 2010.
II. Offensive Speech in the Supreme Court
The Court has long recognized that expression can “sti[r] people to anger,” “strike at prejudices and preconceptions,” and have “profound unsettling effects as it presses for acceptance of an idea.”
Snyder implicates the Court’s offensive speech jurisprudence in its purest sense. The Phelps’ expression was disrespectful, even contemptible, but, as the Fourth Circuit found, it falls squarely within the realm of public discourse.
[The Phelps] have long expressed their religious views by . . . picket[ing]. . . various . . . public events that they view as promoting homosexuality, idolatry, and other sin. . . . [T]hey have also picketed near funerals of gay persons, persons who died from AIDS, people whose lifestyles they believe to be sinful but who are touted as heroic upon their death, and people whose actions while alive had supported homosexuality and other activities they consider proud sin. . . . [The Phelps] believe that one of the great sins of America is idolatry in the form of worshiping the human instead of God and that, in America, this has taken the form of intense worship of the dead, particularly soldiers. . . .
Although the Phelps’ speech is well outside mainstream thought, the Court’s doctrine maintains such expression is part of public discourse. As the Court noted, “[m]ost of what we say to one another lacks religious, political, scientific, educational, journalistic, historical, or artistic value (let alone serious value), but it is still sheltered from government regulation.”
Furthermore, the negative public reaction to the Phelps’ speech, and arguments favoring imposing tort liability for the Phelps, suggest a strong risk of censorship of their speech. Unlike neutral laws regulating the time, place and manner of any protests near funerals, a lawsuit seeking imposition of damages targets particular individuals or groups and is far more likely a response to the protestors’ offensive messages.
Those arguing for tort liability in Snyder, however, claim that the Phelps’ speech falls within exceptions to the Court’s First Amendment protection. Specifically, they (1) argue that the Court’s captive audience doctrine allows regulation of offensive speech that invades the listener’s privacy, and (2) analogize liability for IIED and invasion of privacy to the Court’s other areas of low value speech, such as libel or fighting words. As discussed below, tort liability based solely on offensive messages would require substantial extension of the Court’s jurisprudence.
III. Exceptions to Free Speech Protection
A. Invasion of Privacy and the Captive Audience
The Court’s captive audience doctrine allows regulation of speech that unreasonably invades the privacy interests of listeners. This aspect of the Court’s jurisprudence is most clearly associated with the home, where privacy protection is at its apex.
When the listener is in a public space, however, the Court is far less willing to recognize a captive audience. It rejected the notion that individuals have a “generalized right to be left alone on a public street or sidewalk.”
Supporters of tort liability, however, argue that mourners at a funeral have a privacy interest “at least as significant as the privacy interes[t] at stake in one’s home.”
B. Low Value Speech
The Court has carefully crafted its low value speech doctrines to identify narrow categories of speech capable of restriction.
The IIED and invasion of privacy standards Snyder and others advocate do not incorporate these external indicia of harm and, thus, fit poorly within the Court’s low value speech categories. Snyder urges imposition of IIED liability, for example, based upon the common law elements of that tort.
In fact, the Court in Hustler v. Falwell already recognized that the common law standards for IIED do not sufficiently protect free speech values.
The broad invasion of privacy argument embraced by Snyder and others faces similar problems. The common law elements of invasion of privacy typically involve (1) an unauthorized intrusion, (2) into a secluded space or one’s private affairs, (3) that is highly offensive to a reasonable person.
IV. Emotion and the First Amendment
Several observers argue that this emotional impact is precisely the reason why Snyder should recover damages. They claim, for example, that the First Amendment should not protect “the use of words as weapons” and argue allowing tort liability for highly offensive speech will not interfere with robust “public discourse.”
A. The Psychology of Anger
Contrary to conventional and legal wisdom, which often treat emotion as irrational and fleeting, emotions “are determined, in large part, by beliefs.”
Not everyone, however, perceives the same action as demeaning.
People also tend toward particular actions when experiencing particular emotions. Thus, those who experience anger tend to express a greater willingness to attack the offending individual.
B. Emotion, Tort Liability and Snyder
This psychological research reveals just how problematic the civil claims are in Snyder. They are not problematic because emotions such as anger are inherently bad or because emotion has no role in First Amendment doctrine. Indeed, the Court has recognized the important relationship between emotion and expression.
Outrageous action is the core element of IIED. When actions, such as having sexual relations with the spouse of one’s client,
The other elements of IIED do nothing to limit potential censorship. Although the intent requirement superficially limits liability to the worst actors, it does little to protect free speech values. As noted above, an offender’s perceived blameworthiness is a component of an outraged plaintiff’s response—the defendant’s perceived blameworthiness is partly why the plaintiff is angry. Anger also often causes plaintiffs to attribute bad intent to those they want to find blameworthy, whether or not they actually acted with such intent.
Similar censorship problems arise with Snyder’s invasion of privacy argument. Conflating intrusion and offensiveness reduces the question of tort liability to whether speech is offensive to a reasonable person. As with IIED, a plaintiff is most likely offended by speech that interferes with an individual’s values and beliefs. Although invasion of privacy also requires an intrusion upon seclusion, that concept is malleable
Ultimately, tort liability based solely upon speech that offends or outrages others would chill speech because of its arbitrary and unpredictable nature. Responses to speech are particularized and personal. Anyone may respond with anger, and a lawsuit, to speech they consider a demeaning and personally offensive. To be sure, most offensive speech will not satisfy the elements of IIED or invasion of privacy. But any contentious speech perceived to be personally directed—such as criticism of one’s religion, criticism of military efforts, or burning the flag—could be the basis for a tort suit. The capricious nature of such lawsuits would cast a pall over public debate.
The existence of a jury, which should filter truly frivolous claims of offense or outrage, also cannot prevent this chilling effect. Juries cannot prevent the potential filing of such lawsuits, which alone chills public discourse.
The arousal of moralistic anger is not confined to injustices perpetrated against one’s self. Witnessing the harming of a third party can also arouse strong feelings of anger and injustice. . . . Individuals are committed to the “ought forces” of their moral community . . . and people believe these forces deserve respect from all members of the community. The violation of these forces represents an insult to the integrity of the community and provokes both moralistic anger and the urge to punish the offender in its members.
A jury will most likely experience “moralistic anger” when a speaker violates otherwise widely held social norms, such as protesting near another’s funeral. While the emotional response of jurors may be an issue in any trial, it is uniquely concerning in First Amendment cases. Juries in civil tort suits are likely to punish unpopular speakers precisely because they are unpopular. Such a result runs counter to First Amendment tenets because it silences particular viewpoints
Conclusion
If the Phelps were noisy or disruptive, officials could justifiably regulate their protests. Civil liability for IIED and invasion of privacy might also be appropriate if the Phelps’ expression contained threats, intentional lies or other external indicia of harm.
Christina Wells, Enoch H. Crowder Professor of Law, University of Missouri School of Law. I am indebted to Heidi Kitrosser, Lyrissa Lidsky, Caroline Malla Corbin, Jen Robbennolt, Charles Smith, Jesse Frogge, Slone Isselhard, and the participants at the 2010 Annual Meeting of the Law & Society Association, where I presented an earlier version of this paper. Thanks also to Gina Harrison, Heath Hooper and Dave Winters for their research assistance. I co-authored and submitted an amicus brief to the Supreme Court in Snyder v. Phelps. See Brief of Amici Curiae Scholars of First Amendment Law in Support of Respondent Phelps, Snyder v. Phelps, No. 09-751 (U.S. July 14, 2010).
- Lizette Alvarez, Outrage At Funeral Protests Pushes Lawmakers to Act, N.Y. Times, Apr. 17, 2006, at A14 (quoting Indiana Representative Steve Buyer describing Phelps’ behavior as “repugnant, outrageous, [and] despicable”). Others refer to the Phelpses as “pieces of garbage” and “evil.” Geoff Oldfather, A Good Way to Handle Westboro Protestors: Ignore Them, Fort Pierce Trib. (Fla.), May 22, 2008, at B6 (available at 2008 WLNR 9706446); Michael Bearak, Westboro Baptist Church Is Evil, Digital J., Apr. 11, 2010, http://www.digitaljournal.com/article/290434. ↑
- 580 F.3d 206 (4th Cir. 2009), cert. granted 130 S. Ct. 1737 (2010). ↑
- Mr. Snyder sued Fred Phelps and several others, including Mr. Phelps daughters, Shirley Phelps-Roper and Rebekah Phelps-Davis. See id. at 211-12. ↑
- Snyder v. Phelps, 533 F. Supp. 2d 567, 572. ↑
- Christina E. Wells, Privacy and Funeral Protests, 87 N.C. L. Rev. 151, 153 (2008). ↑
- 580 F.3d at 212 (noting that the Phelps maintained a distance of several hundred feet from the funeral and were not noisy or disruptive). ↑
- See, e.g., Hill v. Colorado, 530 U.S. 703, 716 (2000); Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement, 505 U.S. 123, 134-35 (1992); Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 414 (1989). ↑
- See infra Part III. ↑
- Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15, 21 (1971). ↑
- Richard J. Lazarus, Emotion & Adaptation 217, 222 (1991). ↑
- Id. at 226. ↑
- Terry A. Maroney, Emotional Common Sense as Constitutional Law, 62 Vand. L. Rev. 851, 892 (2009). ↑
- See infra note 56 and Part III.B. ↑
- Snyder v. Phelps, 533 F. Supp. 2d 567, 571-72 (D. Md. 2008) (describing the Phelps’ view that “God hates homosexuality and hates and punishes America for its tolerance of homosexuality, particularly in the United States military”); Wells, supra note __, at 160 & n.44. ↑
- Snyder v. Phelps, 580 F.3d 206, 212 (4th Cir. 2009). See also Wells, supra note 3, at 161-74. ↑
- Snyder v. Phelps, 580 F.3d 206, 211-12 (4th Cir. 2009). ↑
- See id. at 212. ↑
- Id. ↑
- Id. at 212 (describing the “The Burden of Marine Lance Cpl. Matthew Snyder”). ↑
- Brief for Petitioner at 7-8, Snyder v. Phelps, No. 09-751 (U.S. May 24, 2010); 580 F.3d at 212. ↑
- 580 F.3d at 212. ↑
- Id. at 213; Brief for Petitioner, supra note 12, at 8. ↑
- The court dismissed Snyder’s defamation and publicity given to private life claims. 580 F.3d at 212-13. ↑
- Id. at 214-15. ↑
- Id. (quoting Joint Appendix at 3113-14). ↑
- Id. at 211. ↑
- 533 F. Supp. 2d at 577, 579. ↑
- 580 F.3d at 218 (citing Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co., 497 U.S. 1, 20 (1990)). ↑
- Id. at 223. ↑
- Id. at 226 (quotations omitted). ↑
- 130 S.Ct.. 1737 (Mar. 8, 2010) (No. 09-751). ↑
- Terminiello v. City of Chicago, 337 U.S. 1, 4 (1949). ↑
- Hill v. Colorado, 530 U.S. 703, 716 (2000); see also Forsyth County v. Nationalist Movement, 505 U.S. 123, 134-35 (1992); Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 414 (1989); Boos v. Barry, 485 U.S. 312, 322 (1988); Hustler Magazine v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46, 55-56 (1988); Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15, 21; Street v. New York, 394 U.S. 576, 592 (1969); Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.S. 296, 310 (1940). ↑
- Terminiello, 337 U.S. at 4 (“The vitality of civil and political institutions in our society depends on free discussion . . . . [A] function of free speech under our system of government is to invite dispute.”). ↑
- Cohen, 403 U.S. at 21 (Indiscriminate punishment of offensive speech “effectively empower[s] a majority to silence dissidents simply as a matter of personal predilections.”). ↑
- 580 F.3d at 222-23. ↑
- See supra notes 3 & 20. ↑
- Media outlets regularly address these issues. See, e.g., Rod Nordland, 12 NATO Soldiers, 7 From U.S., are Killed in Afghanistan, N.Y. Times, June 8, 2010, at A11; Christopher Hitchens, Bring the Pope to Justice, Newsweek, Apr. 23, 2010; Peter Moskos, Don’t Ask, Don’t Tell: Farewell to My Father’s Idea, Wash. Post, June 4, 2010, at A17; Maura Dolan, Bid to Ban Gay Marriage Will Stay On Ballot, California Supreme Court Rules, L.A. Times, July 17, 2008. ↑
- Phelps-Roper v. Bruning, No. 4:10CV3131, 2010 WL 2723202, at *1 (D. Neb. July 6, 2010). ↑
- United States v. Stevens, 130 S. Ct. 1577, 1591 (2010) (citation omitted) (original emphasis). ↑
- Christina E. Wells, Bringing Structure to the Law of Injunctions Against Expression, 51 Case West. Res. L. Rev. 1, 32-33 (2000) (discussing how broadly applicable neutral statutes better protect against censorship compared to restrictions applicable to particular individuals). ↑
- FCC v. Pacifica Found., 438 U.S. 726, 745 (1978); see also Boos, 485 U.S. at 322; Cohen, 403 U.S. at 22-24. ↑
- Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474, 484 (1988). ↑
- Pacifica, 438 U.S. 726, 750; Rowan v. U.S. Post Office Dep’t., 397 U.S. 728, 738 (1970). ↑
- Frisby, 487 U.S. at 486 (citation omitted). ↑
- Schenck v. Pro-Choice Network, 519 U.S. 357, 383 (1997) (citation omitted). For elaboration of this argument, see Wells, supra note 3, at 200-12, 228-30. ↑
- Madsen v. Women’s Health Ctr., Inc., 512 U.S. 753, 772 (1994) (upholding restriction on noisy protests around medical clinic); Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U.S. 104, 121 (1972) (upholding restriction on noisy/disruptive protests around schools); Schenck, 519 U.S. 357, 384-85 (upholding injunction restricting protestors based on previous harassing and intimidating conduct); Hill v. Colorado, 530 U.S. 703, 718 n.25 (2000) (upholding eight-foot no-approach zone based on unwanted physical approaches of an individual at close range). ↑
- Madsen, 512 U.S. at 773 (refusing to uphold an injunction banning “images observable” by persons within medical clinics because the only “plausible reason” such signs disturbed patients was if they “found the expression contained in such images disagreeable”). ↑
- See, e.g., Erznoznik v. City of Jacksonville, 422 U.S. 205, 210-11 (1975) (quoting Cohen, 403 U.S. at 21). ↑
- Brief for the State of Kansas, 47 Other States, and the District of Columbia as Amici Curiae in Support of Petitioner, at 13, Snyder v. Phelps, No. 09-751 (U.S. June 1, 2010). See also Brief for Petitioner, supra note 12, at 53. ↑
- Brief for the State of Kansas, supra note 38, at 13-17; Brief for Petitioner, supra note 12, at 52-53. State officials defending funeral protest laws make similar arguments. Wells, supra note, 3, at 214-17. ↑
- Wells, supra note 3, at 228. ↑
- Frisby, 487 U.S. at 486-87 (finding that “[t]he devastating effect of targeted picketing on the quiet enjoyment of the home is beyond doubt). ↑
- Id. at 482-84. ↑
- Several amicus briefs openly seek regulation of the content of the Phelps’ message. Brief for the State of Kansas, supra note 38, at 15 (describing the Phelps’ signs as “personal and vicious attacks, fully intended to target the mourners”); Brief for the Veterans of Foreign Wars of the United States as Amicus Curiae in Support of Petitioner, at 10, Snyder v. Phelps, No. 09-751 (U.S. June 1, 2010) (stating that the “First Amendment does not require the grieving family to endure offensive speech of a personally abusive nature”). Snyder, however, argues that the Phelps’ mere presence at the funeral violated his privacy at a time when he was mourning and emotionally vulnerable. Brief for Petitioner, supra note 12, at 8-9. But this argument is grounded in the content of the Phelps’ speech. There is nothing inherently offensive about peaceful, nondisruptive protests near a funeral; protests occurred in association with funerals well before the Phelps’ activities. See, e.g., Joyce L. Kornbluh, Rebel Voices: An IWW Anthology 200 (1964) (discussing the 1913 funeral/protest of two workers killed by private detectives); Violent Protests Erupt After Funeral, Orlando Sentinel, March 26, 2000, at A4 (discussing protest involving 3,000 marchers following funeral of man shot by police). Furthermore, Snyder welcomed protestors with a supportive message. See Brief in Opposition to Petition for Writ of Cert. at 6-7, Snyder v. Phelps, No. 09-751 (U.S. Jan. 20, 2010) (describing the well-received “picketing” of school children and the Patriot Guard Riders at the Snyder funeral). Thus, the Phelps’ speech is “inappropriate” only because of their disrespectful and hurtful message. ↑
- Those categories include incitement of illegal action, fighting words, defamation, fraud, true threats, obscenity, child pornography, and speech integral to criminal conduct. See Stevens, 130 S. Ct. at 1585-6. ↑
- Id. at 1586. ↑
- See, e.g., Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397 (1989); Terminiello v. City of Chicago, 337 U.S. 1, 4-5 (1949). ↑
- Daniel Farber, The Categorical Approach to Protecting Speech in American Constitutional Law, 84 Ind. L.J. 917, 933 (2009) (“[T]he large majority of proscribed speech adds little or nothing to public discourse . . . partly because the [Court’s] ‘narrow tailoring’ requirement. . . [forces] the state to focus on speech that has little function except to threaten the government’s compelling interest [such as preventing violence or preserving individual reputation].”). ↑
- Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444, 447(1969). ↑
- Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U.S. 518, 523 (1972). ↑
- Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 349__ __(1974) (refusing to allow presumed or punitive damages absent a finding that defendant acted with “knowledge of falsity or reckless disregard for the truth”). ↑
- Hustler Magazine v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46, 56 (1988); see also Bose Corp. v. Consumers Union of United States, Inc., 466 U.S. 485, 505 (1984) (describing Court review as designed “to confine the perimeters of any unprotected category within acceptably narrow limits in an effort to ensure that protected expression will not be inhibited”). ↑
- Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 412 (1989) (quotation omitted). See also Falwell, 485 U.S. at 55. ↑
- Brief for Petitioner, supra note 12, at 21-41 (arguing against imposition of First Amendment standards in Snyder’s IIED case). ↑
- See, e.g., Pemberton v. Bethlehem Steel Corp., 502 A.2d 1101, 1115 (Md. Ct. Spec. App. 1986). ↑
- Falwell, 485 U.S. at 56. Falwell involved common law standards nearly identical to Maryland’s standards. 485 U.S. at 50 n.3. ↑
- Id. at 55. ↑
- Id. at 53 (quoting Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U.S. 64, 73 (1964)). ↑
- Id. ↑
- Restatement (Second) of Torts § 652B (1965) (defining intrusion branch of privacy as “intentionally intrud[ing], physically or otherwise, upon the solitude of another or his private affairs or concerns . . . [when] the intrusion would be highly offensive to a reasonable person”). ↑
- See, e.g., 1 J. Thomas McCarthy, The Rights of Publicity and Privacy § 5:89 (2d. ed. 2010) (Intrusion usually “involves some physical, not merely psychological, incursion into one’s privacy,” including invasion of space around a person via surveillance or stalking.); Restatement (Second) of Torts § 652B cmt b (Intrusion requires physical intrusion into a place of plaintiff’s seclusion or “by the use of the defendant’s senses, with or without mechanical aids, to oversee or overhear the plaintiff’s private affairs.”); Schulman v. Group W Prods., Inc., 955 P. 2d 469, 490 (Cal. 1998) (“[P]laintiff must show the defendant penetrated some zone of physical or sensory privacy surrounding, or obtained unwanted access to data about, the plaintiff. The tort is proven only if the plaintiff had an objectively reasonable expectation of seclusion or solitude in the place, conversation or data source.”). ↑
- 491 U.S. 397 at 412 (quotation omitted). ↑
- Jeffrey Shulman, Free Speech at What Cost?: Snyder v. Phelps and Speech-Based Tort Liability, 2010 Cardozo L. Rev. de novo 313, 336; see also Chelsea Brown, Not Your Mother’s Remedy:A Civil Action Response to the Westboro Baptist Church’s Military Funeral Demonstrations, 112 W. Va. L. Rev. 207, 232 (2009); Brief for the State of Kansas, supra note 38, at 23-24, 33-34. ↑
- Shulman, supra note 56, at 336. ↑
- Maroney, supra note 7, at 891. Conventional legal wisdom often treats emotion as unpredictable and visceral. See Neal R. Feigenson, Sympathy and Legal Judgment: A Psychological Analysis, 65 Tenn. L. Rev. 1, 15 (1997). ↑
- Maroney, supra note 7, at 874; see also Craig A. Smith & Richard S. Lazarus, Emotion and Adaptation, in Handbook of Personality: Theory and Research 609, 611 (Lawrence A. Pervin ed., 1990). ↑
- Phoebe C. Ellsworth & Klaus R. Scherer, Appraisal Processes in Emotion, in Handbook of Affective Sciences 572, 572 (Richard J. Davidson et al., eds. 2003). ↑
- Lazarus, supra note 5, at 81-82; Phoebe C. Ellsworth & Craig A. Smith, From Appraisal to Emotion: Differences Among Unpleasant Feelings, 12 Motivation and Emotion 271, 272 (1988); Matthias Siemer et al., Same Situation—Different Emotions: How Appraisals Shape Our Emotions, 7 Emotion 592, 598 (2007). ↑
- Mahoney, supra note __, at 892. ↑
- Lazarus, supra note 5, at 222; Paul Ekman, Antecedent Events and Emotion Metaphors, in The Nature of Emotion: Fundamental Questions 146, 147 (P. Ekman & R. Davidson eds., 1994). ↑
- Smith & Lazarus, supra note 59, at 616 (“Appraisals are strongly influenced by personality variables. Two individuals can construe their situations quite similarly (agree on all the facts) and yet react with very different emotions, because they have appraised the adaptational significance of those facts differently.”) ↑
- Id. at 625. ↑
- Lazarus, supra note 5, at 222-23; Gerald Clore, Andrew Ortney & Allan Collins, The Cognitive Structure of Emotions 146-54 (1988). See also Gerald L. Clore & Karen Gasper, Feeling Is Believing: Some Affective Influences on Belief, in Emotions and Beliefs: How Feelings Influence Thoughts 10, 30 (Nico H. Frijda et al. eds., 2000); Siemer et al., supra note 61, at 595. ↑
- Smith & Lazarus, supra note 59, at 627; Ellsworth & Scherer, supra note 60, at 581. ↑
- Dale T. Miller, Disrespect and the Experience of Injustice, 52 Ann. Rev. Psychol. 527, 533 (2001). ↑
- Lazarus, supra note 5, at 226; see Ellsworth & Smith, supra note 61, at 296. ↑
- See, e.g., Dov Cohen et al., Insult, Aggression, and the Southern Culture of Honor: An “Experimental Ethnography,” 70 J. Person. & Soc. Psych. 945 (1996) (studying insults to honor among Southern & Northern males and linking propensity for hostile reaction to insults to whether one had grown up in Southern “honor” culture). ↑
- Miller, supra note 67, at 544 (noting that desire for retribution is a motivator for lawsuits and that disrespectful treatment can increase people’s willingness to avail themselves of formal avenues of redress); see also Ellsworth & Smith, supra note 61, at 301 (noting that angry people might seek less aggressive, more socially acceptable means of retaliation if they are influenced by other factors). ↑
- Cohen, 403 U.S. at 26 (noting that “words are often chosen as much for their emotive as their cognitive force”). ↑
- Figueiredo-Torres v. Nickel, 321 Md. 642, 657-68 (1991) (upholding IIED claim against psychologist who had sexual relations with patient’s wife). ↑
- Clore & Gasper, supra note 65, at 30 (noting that “emotional feeling can then increase certainty or commitment”). ↑
- Boos, 485 U.S. at 322 (finding unconstitutional a law prohibiting the display of signs tending to bring foreign governments into public odium or disrepute); Cohen, 403 U.S. at 22-24 (states cannot censor citizens to promote public civility); Johnson, 491 U.S. at 415 (state cannot regulate flag burning to promote respect for the flag). ↑
- Clore, Ortney & Collins, supra note 65, at 151; Miller, supra note 67, at 537. ↑
- It is perhaps not surprising that Falwell rejected the intent standard of IIED as insufficiently protective of speech. 485 U.S. at 53 (quoting Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U.S. 64, 73 (1964)). ↑
- Although emotional distress can manifest in physical symptoms (occasionally required in order to recover in some jurisdictions), such symptoms are not objective indicia of harm in the same way as threats, violence or other indicia involved in the Court’s low value speech categories or captive audience doctrine. Physical symptoms, although more tangible than emotional harm, still emanate from the listeners’ response to the offensive message. Such a response is not consistent with the Court’s conception of low value speech as speech that, by definition, does not contribute to public discourse.. ↑
- Wells, supra note 3, at 181-82 (“recognizing relative zones of privacy involves a delicate balance of preserving social interaction while carving out necessary spaces of refuge in public”); McCarthy, supra note 55, § 5:98 (noting that zones of seclusion are a product of “custom and usage” rather than of objective factors). ↑
- See supra note 17 and accompanying text. ↑
- Like a vague statute, the lack of notice associated with lawsuits based on offensive speech subjects potential defendants to arbitrary and inconsistent enforcement. Smith v. Goguen, 415 U.S. 566, 573-74 (1974) (finding that a flag contempt statute “fails to draw reasonably clear lines between the kinds of nonceremonial treatment that are criminal and those that are not”); see also Eugene Volokh, Freedom of Speech and the Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress Tort, 2010 Cardozo L. Rev. de novo 300, 302 (2010) (“[T]he vagueness of the ‘outrageousness’ standard exacerbates the risk that the emotional distress tort will deter . . . speech.” ) ↑
- New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 278 (1964) (discussing that threat of litigation may create a “pall of fear and timidity imposed upon those who would give voice to public criticism” and “an atmosphere in which the First Amendment freedoms cannot survive”). ↑
- Miller, supra note 67, at 535. ↑
- Edwards v. South Carolina, 372 U.S. 229, 237 (1963) (“The Fourteenth Amendment does not permit a State to. . . [punish] the peaceful expression of unpopular views.”). ↑
- Terminiello, 337 U.S. at 4-5. See also Robert Post, The Constitutional Concept of Public Discourse: Outrageous Opinion, Democratic Deliberation, and Hustler Magazine v. Falwell, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 603, 632 (1990). ↑
- See, e.g., Brief of Scholars of First Amendment Law, supra note , at 26-32 (discussing appropriate standards for imposing IIED and invasion of privacy liability on speech); Brief of the American Civil Liberties Union and the American Civil Liberties Union of Maryland as Amici Curiae* in Support of Respondents at 26-27, Snyder v. Phelps, No. 09-751, (U.S. July 14, 2010) (embracing Fourth Circuit’s “provably false” statement of fact standard). ↑
- See, e.g., Falwell, 485 U.S. at 53. ↑